Romanticism

Start Free Trial

Romantic Ideas in Current Attitudes About Nature and the Environment

Download PDF PDF Page Citation Cite Share Link Share

Last Updated on May 6, 2015, by eNotes Editorial. Word Count: 1561

Romantic odes may be out of style, and few novels are now written in the style of Jane Austen or Mary Wollstonecraft Shelley, but some romantic ideas and ideals are still deeply embedded in our own popular culture, particularly in popular attitudes about nature. Most people do not know it, but our current ideas about the environment and our relationship to it were born during the romantic era.

The Birth of Environmentalism in Romanticism For the romantics, the vast, uncontrolled wilderness of nature was a holy place, a place where people could retreat from the increasing filth and falsity of civilization. Nature was viewed as “wiser” than humans; it had existed since before humans existed and, if left alone, would continue to flourish. Humans could not produce anything as complex, beautiful, and grand as nature, and they could certainly not improve on anything nature had created. However, by going to wild places, people could align themselves with the harmony and wisdom inherent in nature, and be renewed.

In addition, ecological movements encourage people to think of themselves as kindred to, and part of, the natural world, rather than standing apart from it. This feeling of kinship and oneness is a hallmark of Romanticism.

These views, which persist in our own culture, were new during the romantic era. Until the eighteenth century, people had little time to spare for appreciating nature; they were busy farming, fighting wars, and simply trying to survive. However, the Industrial Revolution gave the new urban middle class time for recreation. It also resulted in pollution and overcrowding in the cities, so these people looked to natural areas, rather than the increasingly unpleasant urban ones, for their recreation. Gardening, nature walks, and appreciation of natural beauty became common pastimes for the first time in history. As Lucy Moore writes in the Ecologist, “For the first time, nature became an object, and this may be the moment the modern environmental movement began.”

The Influence of Romantic Writers Through the influence of romantic writers, ordinary people became interested in experiencing nature. For example, Wordsworth, who wrote poems about the beauty and spirituality of nature, was a highly successful poet in his own lifetime and was even appointed poet laureate in 1843, but his guides to the area where he lived were even more popular than his collections of poetry. He lived in the Lake District of England, and his writings about the natural beauty of the area made the Lake District a tourist attraction in the mid-1800s. Travelers visited the area hoping to partake of the same natural beauty, inspiration, and spiritual renewal the poet describes in his writings. Although it seems commonplace now to retreat to nature for renewal, at the time this was a novel idea, and walking in the Lake District and perhaps encountering the poet on his own walks became a kind of fad of the romantic era.

Coleridge, who also lived in the area and was a favorite of Lake District tourists, likewise saw nature as a redeeming and purifying force, and loved wilderness and wildness. According to Moore, Coleridge wrote, “The farther I ascend from animated Nature, from men, and cattle, and the common birds of the woods, and fields, the greater becomes in me the intensity of the feeling of Life.”

For a time, Coleridge believed he could build a utopian community that would partake of the spiritually purifying aspects of nature, and he and Robert Southey planned to construct such a community on the then-wild banks of the Susquehanna River in Pennsylvania. Although, like many such utopian dreams, the plan...

(This entire section contains 1561 words.)

See This Study Guide Now

Start your 48-hour free trial to unlock this study guide. You'll also get access to more than 30,000 additional guides and more than 350,000 Homework Help questions answered by our experts.

Get 48 Hours Free Access

ultimately fell through, Coleridge retained his belief that nature could provide solace and wisdom to people.

Percy Shelley, who was not quite as active in outdoor pursuits, nevertheless wrote, “I love all waste / And solitary places, where we taste / The pleasure of believing what we see / Is boundless, as we wish our souls to be.”

Mary Wollstonecraft Shelley reflected the romantic view of nature as a place of peace and redemption in Frankenstein. In the book, unlike in the films based on it, the monster is a peaceful and gentle creature. When the monster discovers how cruel humans are, it dreams of fleeing to South America, where it will live peacefully in the forest with a mate Dr. Frankenstein will make for it. They will live simply on the fruits and nuts of the forest, sleeping among the trees: a romantic ideal, a return to the spiritual innocence and purity of the Garden of Eden. However, Dr. Frankenstein, who is afraid of the monster’s potential, destroys the female, forcing the monster back to civilization—and civilization’s destruction.

Keats was also keenly aware of the destructive human impact on nature, and that appreciation of nature often occurs only when people become aware that natural beauty is fragile and can be destroyed and lost forever. In short, the romantics believed that untouched nature invoked a sense of awe and grandeur within people; that experiencing this awe could allow people to experience a feeling of purification and redemption; that untouched nature was superior to humanity; and that the long-term presence of people in nature could only be detrimental to it.

These principles have long guided attitudes toward the preservation and use of wilderness areas, and continue to the present day. The U.S. Wilderness Act of 1964 provides for the protection and preservation of areas untouched or little-touched by human intervention, where humans can merely be temporary visitors, and where permanent human settlement or construction is not allowed. This idea of nature as pristine and separate from the degrading presence of people goes back to the romantics.

In addition, most campers and hikers have heard the popular phrase “leave no trace,” which urges people to minimize their impact on nature to such an extent that, after they leave the wilderness area, it would be difficult or impossible for observers to tell that they were even there. Campers are asked to carry out everything they carry in, and to “take only pictures; leave only footprints” behind. While in the wilderness, people are also asked to respect wildlife by keeping their distance from it, to be as quiet as possible so that the sounds of nature are the only ones heard, and to avoid crowding or overusing any one area. As R. Bruce Hall notes in the Journal of Leisure Research, this philosophy, like other currently prevalent wilderness-use principles, “encourages people to think of themselves as temporary visitors whose presence can only harm nature. . . . [and] emphasize[s] the negative consequences people have on natural areas and on recreation experience.” It also emphasizes the benefits that people can gain from experiencing nature in its purest, least-disturbed state.

Getting and Spending: The Impact of Industry Wordsworth wrote in his poem “The World Is Too Much With Us,” “Getting and spending, we lay waste our powers; / Little we see in nature that is ours; / We have given our hearts away, a sordid boon!” What he means is that in the frenzy of economic expansion and exploitation of the environment, people have lost touch with the spiritual and creative powers that true contact with nature can provide. Thus, we are out of touch with both the environment and ourselves.

The Industrial Revolution began over two hundred years ago, but we are still experiencing it and its effects on society and nature; the problems of pollution and waste have only increased since that time as industry has grown and become ever more complex. According to James Pinkerton in Foreign Affairs, David Malin Rodman of the World-Watch Institute, an environmental group, noted that it is “the very nature of industrial economic systems to degrade the environment on which they depend.” This idea first became prevalent during the Industrial Revolution, when coal-fired factories began spewing black smoke over England’s green countryside and dumping toxic wastes into previously clean rivers.

This worry about the negative effects of industry is still widely held today. Toward the end of the twentieth century, with increasing environmental destruction, people became increasingly aware that irreplaceable natural treasures were being degraded or lost, and increasing numbers of species were becoming extinct. Pinkerton writes, “Many people have become aware that unbounded cultivation, extraction, and construction have disastrously degraded the ecosystem of the planet.”

As a result of this awareness, previously marginalized ecologically-based political movements, often rooted in romantic ideas about nature, grew and gained so many adherents that they became a part of mainstream political debate. In 1997 in Europe, according to Pinkerton, the ecological political parties had a potential electorate that was almost as large as that of the Christian democratic parties. In the United States, Green Party candidate Ralph Nader came in fourth in the 1996 presidential election and came in second in many areas that were heavily populated by college students. In 2000 Nader came in third in the national election, and some observers claimed that his presence on the ballot diverted a substantial number of voters from the Democratic Party and thus lost the election for Democratic candidate Al Gore. These victories for the environmental parties show that many people, like Wordsworth, Coleridge, Shelley, and other romantics, still believe that nature, as a source of renewal, transcendence, and peace, should be celebrated and protected.

Source: Kelly Winters, Critical Essay on Romanticism, in Literary Movements for Students, The Gale Group, 2003.

The Language of Interpretation in Romantic Poetry: A Strong Working of the Mind

Download PDF PDF Page Citation Cite Share Link Share

Last Updated on May 6, 2015, by eNotes Editorial. Word Count: 9485

I In 1799 William Blake reminded the Reverend Dr. Trusler, “The wisest of the Ancients considerd what is not too Explicit as the fittest for Instruction, because it rouzes the faculties to act.” This comment may be applied to the rhetorical activity of much Romantic poetry as well, especially in poems in which logical structures—the plots of an argument, a tale, or an informing legend—are the expected means of instruction. The Rime of the Ancient Mariner, The Thorn, “La Belle Dame sans Merci,” and “Ode on a Grecian Urn” all unfold mysteries against potential sources of interpretation: moral lessons, arguments, glosses, village testimony, portentous encounters, spectral legends. Yet however much such sources may “rouze” the mind to render intelligible “what is not too Explicit,” in these poems, the materials invoked for that purpose themselves become invaded by what Keats calls “uncertainties, Mysteries, doubts.” If these poems arouse expectation that there is a secure logic to be discovered for their perplexing circumstances, they tend to dramatize the difficulties of such discovery more than its success.

These are poems, in other words, about problems in interpretation, involving questions that go to the heart of the Romantic concern with language itself: What is the status of explication or logical argument in poems that appear to frustrate such modes of discourse even as they put them forth? What kind of poem, or poetry, does this activity produce? One effect, certainly, is to cast into doubt the principles of coherence (the causal sequences) on which plots and arguments alike rely and to foreground the less certain, uneasy motions of mind attempting to describe such principles in the circumstances that have compelled its attention. Such stress yields a poetic syntax more psychological than logical in organization, more affective than narrative in its procedures. These poems all show the degree to which interpretation cannot consist simply of deciphering hidden patterns of meaning or discovering causal sequences, but must become an active seeking and generating of meaning.

The Rime of the Ancient Mariner and The Thorn dramatizes the efforts of their speakers to elucidate mystery through recourse to the logic of moral argument and the logic of narrative, respectively. The Mariner’s “Rime” itself involves several kinds of interpretation, but the most blatant sense-making scheme in Coleridge’s text—the Marginal Gloss—is amassed against the Mariner’s “Rime” as a parallel commentary, making the poem as a whole bear the signature of two distinct intelligences: that of the riming Mariner and that of the Marginal Editor. In The Thorn, Wordsworth entertains dilemmas of interpretation in the body of the poem itself; moreover, he diminishes the locutional differences between the narrator of the tale and the voice of his logic-seeking questioner—as if to suggest a unity of enterprise. In both these Lyrical Ballads, the sources of interpretive authority and the logical patterns they promote or delineate never quite emerge as “points and resting places in reasoning” independent of “the fluxes and refluxes of the mind” trying to interpret.

So psychological an emphasis (and the poetic texture it effects) must have impressed Wordsworth and Coleridge alike as a revolutionary enough experiment in the language of poetry. Yet Coleridge’s belief that “the best part of human language . . . is derived from reflection on the acts of the mind itself” was not to be given its most radical poetic treatment until a generation later. Keats explicitly features the questions of interpretation that haunt The Rime of the Ancient Mariner and The Thorn in his own lyrical ballad “La Belle Dame sans Merci”—a poem that bears a structural resemblance to The Thorn. Not long after, he was at work on a series of odes (of which “Ode on a Grecian Urn” is the most striking example) in which he not only makes a premise of the problems of interpretation all these Lyrical Ballads trace with increasing intensity, but extends that negotiation with uncertainty to the reader’s engagement with the play of his rhyme.

II Today, most readers of The Rime of the Ancient Mariner are probably not as bothered as was Coleridge’s acquaintance, the poet and essayist Mrs. Barbauld, about the “improbable” nature of his story. The second “fault” of which she complained to the author, however, remains something of a notorious vexation for many modern readers— namely, that the poem “had no moral.” Coleridge is willing to cede the point on “probability”; but “as to the want of a moral,” he counters, the poem’s “chief fault, if I might say so, was the obtrusion of the moral sentiment so openly on the reader as a principle or cause of action in a work of pure imagination.” Yet in The Rime of the Ancient Mariner Coleridge not only seems to deplore “moral sentiment”; in this work of pure imagination, he seems to want to baffle the effort to discover any principle of action. Indeed, he continues his remarks by declaring that his poem “ought to have no more moral than the Arabian Nights tale of the merchant’s sitting down to eat dates by the side of a well and throwing the shells aside, and lo! a genie starts up and says he must kill the aforesaid merchant because one of the date shells had, it seems, put out the eye of the genie’s son.” Coleridge emphasizes the causal vocabulary with knowing irony, for to the mind of the date-eater, the genie has produced moral necessity from a chance event and consequence.

But before considering what kind of moral paradigm that tale offers to the reader of Coleridge’s poem, we need to turn to the Mariner himself, who finds moral uncertainties in the central circumstance of his “Rime.” The world he describes, as readers from Wordsworth to the present have noted, is one informed by inscrutable forces; nature is unpredictably solicitous or persecutory, benevolent or tyrannous. As in “Dejection,” the language that can be read from nature’s appearances often seems barely more than the fiction of a desperate imagination. Indeed, the foggy atmosphere from which the Albatross emerges, and which always surrounds its presence, suggests both inner and outer weather:

At length did cross an Albatross, Thorough the fog it came; As if it had been a Christian soul, We hailed it God’s name. Despite

the appealing rhyme of “Albatross” with “cross” (here and subsequently), the Mariner’s “As if” has the effect of raising a question about what “principle or cause of action” (if any) is actually involved. For the conjecture, uttered in fogbound misery, seems to describe primarily the hopes of an anxious crew, rather than anything positive about the bird itself. The Mariner and crew attempt repeatedly to convert conjecture into a syntax of event and consequence that can join the Albatross to the fate of their ship: when the splitting of the ice and the rising of a good south wind follow the advent of the bird, they hail it as the agent of their release; when the fog disperses (along with the ice and snow) after the Mariner kills the bird, the crewmen reinterpret the Albatross as the cause of the fog, and their release into sunshine and fair breezes as a consequence of its death; and when the same breezes fail and the “glorious” sun becomes “bloody,” the crewmen imagine themselves plagued by the Mariner’s killing of the Albatross and rue that act. What are we to make of this continual shuffling of logic? Even Wordsworth, usually not averse to making the reader “struggle,” sides with Coleridge’s perplexed readers and against his “Friend” in the “Note to the Ancient Mariner” he wrote for the second edition of Lyrical Ballads. He cites, among other difficulties, the “defect” “that the events having no necessary connection do not produce each other.” The arbitrary interpretations that gather around the Albatross are a case in point. Each new scheme of causality does not clarify any “necessary connection” between the bird and the state of the weather, as much as all together expose the fiction of interpretive acts: ascertainment of the bird’s value emerges after the fact, as a logic of cause and effect is imposed on a mere sequence of events. As in the tale of the genie and the date-eater, cause and effect are matters of convenient collation rather than of inevitable connection. We begin to sense that if the Albatross signifies anything, it is the very ambiguity of signs—that is, the ambiguity with which the external world vexes a desire for interpretive certainty.

The language of cause and consequence not only surrounds the Albatross but is the very principle upon which a narrative must proceed, and so the problem of collation and connection extends to the listener of the Mariner’s tale. How is one supposed to coordinate the two key events upon which his story depends: the killing of the Albatross and the blessing of the snakes? The way the Mariner himself represents these acts makes more of their irrationality than of their moral dimensions: “I shot the ALBATROSS” merely joins subject and predicate, rather than explains the act; and even when that act is apparently redeemed by the blessing of the water- snakes, this, too, is given without reference to a conscious motivation: “I blessed them unaware.” The parallel syntax of “I shot” and “I blessed” does make a neat pattern for the sampler homily with which the Mariner caps his tale: “He prayeth best, who loveth best / All things both great and small: / For the dear God who loveth us, / He made and loveth all.” Nonetheless, a listener cannot escape awareness that this moral is for its bearer embedded in a self-denying context: the Mariner is doomed to eternal exclusion from the love and prayer he preaches. Ironically, he isolates and terrifies his auditors more than he consoles them with any sense of God’s inclusive love. The would-be Wedding-Guest’s “wiser” state notwithstanding, that listener at least is also left “sadder” for having heard the “Rime”—perhaps more “stunned” than instructed by the Mariner’s will over him. Denied the “goodly company” of the marriage feast, the Wedding- Guest’s very name is rendered meaningless. Left “of sense forlorn,” this student of the Mariner’s lesson finds himself, instead, a participant in the Mariner’s alienation: listener and tale-teller alike seem at the end of their encounter “forlorn” of common “sense”—the comfort of living in a world of rational cause and consequence. As Coleridge remarks in the “Conclusion” of his own biography, “there is always a consolatory feeling that accompanies the sense of a proportion between antecedents and consequents . . . giv[ing], as it were, a substratum of permanence, of identity, and therefore of reality, to the shadowy flux of Time.”

What denies the Mariner and all his listeners this sense of proportion is that the question that is the efficient cause of his narration—“What manner of man art thou?”—eludes certain answering. What is his “substratum” of identity? Is he a killer of an Albatross, a blesser of water-snakes, a preacher of God’s love, or an agent of contamination? The question is voiced originally by the Mariner’s first auditor, the Hermit, and as we learn, it wrenches the Mariner “With a woful agony” that requires nothing less than a retelling of all the events of his ordeal. Yet as tortured and elaborate as the Mariner’s response is, it remains indeterminate: the question generates his “Rime,” and his “Rime” regenerates the question. Its conclusion, in fact, gestures toward its perpetual rehearsal in the shadowy flux of time:

Since then, at all uncertain hour, That agony returns: And till my ghastly tale is told, This heart within me burns.

Endlessly navigating about a core of mysterious events, the Mariner can never capture their informing logic: his text circles about this absent center but always begins and concludes in agonizing uncertainty. Nor does Coleridge’s ballad itself secure the tidy closure of “moral sentiment,” ending instead with a register of the aftereffect of the Mariner’s tale in the mind of his stunned, forlorn auditor. If the Mariner himself “Is gone,” he leaves the trace of his mystery in that interior realm, making the truest issue of his “ghastly tale” the way it haunts a listener’s imagination. “I was never so affected with any human Tale,” Charles Lamb wrote to Wordsworth; “After first reading it, I was totally possessed with it for many days. . . the feelings of the man under the operation of such scenery dragged me along like Tom Piper’s magic Whistle.—” Another listener confessed to feeling “insulated” in the wake of hearing the poem recited by its author: “a sea of wonder and mystery flows round [me] as round the spell-stricken ship itself.”

The effect of the Mariner’s “Rime” in leaving its readers thus “possessed,” despite the patent moral at its close, is amplified by the interpretive apparatus with which Coleridge surrounds the text of the “Rime.” The “Argument” at the head of the 1798 poem is primarily descriptive, concerned mainly with the course of the Mariner’s ship and alluding only briefly to “the strange things that befell” as if by chance, accident, or inscrutable agency. With the “Argument” of 1800, however, Coleridge introduces terms of moral logic and potential instruction: “the Ancient Mariner cruelly and in contempt of the laws of hospitality killed a Sea-bird and . . . was followed by many and strange Judgements.” Yet in the 1802 and 1805 editions of Lyrical Ballads Coleridge dropped the “Argument” altogether, as if he had decided not to prejudice his reader with authorial signals, but to let his poem work its own effect. The next publication of the poem in Sibylline Leaves (1817) strikes a compromise, supplying a marginal gloss instead of an argument. Like the “Argument” of 1800, the Gloss often brings a moral interpretation to bear on the Mariner’s story. Unlike the “Argument,” however, the Gloss is a parallel text, in effect competing with the “Rime” for the reader’s attention, rather than supervising it. It presumes to order the Mariner’s ordeal with a logic that his own “Rime” does not disclose—if supplying the “necessary connection[ s]” whose absence Wordsworth, among others, regretted. “And lo! the Albatross proveth a bird of good omen,” it declares with the authority of biblical exegesis. “The ancient Mariner inhospitably killeth the pious bird of good omen,” it avers, judgment in its every other word. Or taking as a cue the Mariner’s fervent hope that “Sure my kind saint took pity on me,” the Gloss confidently interprets a necessary connection: “By grace of the holy Mother, the ancient Mariner is refreshed with rain.” The voice of the Gloss confronts the reader as the genie does the date-eater, starting up to declare moral necessity at every turn. Yet far from clarifying whatever connections between events the “Rime” may have left obscure, the very presence of a Gloss emphasizes their absence and points to the need for explicit terms of instruction in a circumstance where all is interrogative (“Why look’st thou so?” “wherefore stopp’st thou me?” “What manner of man art thou?”). Indeed the final marginal comment, “an agony constraineth . . . [the Mariner] to teach, by his own example, love and reverence to all things that God made and loveth,” gives the rehearsal of that lesson a psychological urgency (“agony”) even as it declares a moral principle. Despite the faith readers such as Robert Penn Warren have placed in the authority of the Gloss, it persists as another fiction—a parallel account of the ordeal recounted by the Mariner’s “Rime,” or an account of another ordeal: the attempt to make sense of the Mariner’s language.

There is one frame, however, that Coleridge retains in every edition, namely, the voice of the anonymous balladeer with which the poem begins and ends. Readers tend, as Lionel Stevenson does, to treat this frame voice as no more than a “perfunctory” device. Yet in a poem so fundamentally involved with issues of tale-telling and tale-listening, this view deserves reconsideration. The relative situation of the Mariner’s “Rime” is what lyricizes the ballad, making it as much about the feelings the “Rime” develops in its tellers and listeners as about the supernatural character of its events or the moral wisdom of its instruction. Its concluding focus on the Wedding-Guest suggests, furthermore, the frame narrator’s muted but overall interest in the relation between “forced” taletelling and “forced” tale-listening. The Wedding- Guest, now possessed with the “Rime,” may have found a motive for narrative similar in power to that which possesses the Mariner with his ordeal.

The poem leaves open to question whether this newly haunted listener might himself become a haunted purveyor of the Rime’s repetitive life: Will the Wedding-Guest rise the morrow morn, compelled to reach toward an audience of his own, to say in the manner of the ballad’s frame narrator, “It is an ancient Mariner, / And he stoppeth one of three”? The ballad’s opening word, “It,” hears the same sense of perplexed indeterminacy with which the Mariner has left the Wedding-Guest, while the present tense of narration, both here and in the ballad’s penultimate stanza (“The Mariner, whose eye is bright, / Whose beard with age is hoar, / Is gone”), suggests the perpetual presence of that figure in the mind that contains his “Rime.” The affinity the balladeer’s language bears to the psychology of the Mariner’s haunted listener is further enhanced by the copresence of their voices in the poem’s inaugural stanza, before the actual character of the Wedding-Guest is introduced. The opening two lines flow immediately into a question —“By thy long grey beard and glittering eye, / Now wherefore stopp’st thou me?”—in which the pattern of meter and rhyme and the as-yet-unspecified identity of the questioner momentarily create the sense of a single mind moving from observation to speech.

The self-circling energies of this narrative frame and the would-be containment offered by the poem’s interpretive frame (the early Argument or later Gloss) suggest an extended rhetorical figure for the motions of a mind left stunned by the Mariner’s “Rime” and attempting to sort out its mystery. Could the interpretive apparatus surrounding what Coleridge thought of as “A Poet’s Reverie” be the textual signatures of a previously sense-forlorn auditor trying to make sense by obtruding (for himself and for his own audience) a “principle of action” on the intolerably inconclusive tale that has possessed his imagination? The Latin epigraph that in 1817 takes the place of earlier Arguments and subtitles indeed brings a problematic perspective to bear on the Mariner’s mysterious experience. An excerpt from Archaelogiae Philosophicae by the Anglican divine, Thomas Burnet, it offers scholarly speculation on the existence of the invisible and the supernatural in the things of the universe. Yet Burnet cautions that in circling about but never attaining knowledge of the unknown, the mind must be vigilant for truth, careful to distinguish the certain from the uncertain. The action of circling about a center that defies final understanding describes the relation of the Mariner’s “Rime” to its enigmatic core of events; it also figures the relation of the Gloss to that “Rime”: each text surrounds a mystery, attempting to negotiate moral certainty in the face of what haunts and rouses the imagination. And the comprehensive text of Coleridge’s 1817 ballad, equivocating between Marginal Gloss and Mariner’s “Rime,” now poses that problem to the reader. For the apparatus criticus and the “Rime” together shape a fuller text that, while denying unambiguous principles of instruction, offers an explicit figure for the ultimate uncertainty of interpretation.

III In leaving its reader so “struggl[ing] with feelings of strangeness and aukwardness,” The Rime of the Ancient Mariner achieves one of the revolutionary goals of Lyrical Ballads. Deriding the “mere artifices of connection” that characterize the “falsity in the poetic style” of the day, Coleridge points to Wordsworth’s contributions to their volume and praises the way such poems reveal compelling “resemblances between that state into which the reader’s mind is thrown” by the “confusion of thought front an unaccustomed train of words and images” and “that state which is induced by the . . . language of empassioned feeling.” The reader’s “confusion” in the presence of such language is the note on which The Thorn begins, and Wordsworth even supplies an interlocutor to give voice to the inevitable protests. The ballad opens plainly enough, with an unspecified speaker reporting a simple fact: “There is a thorn.” But as in The Rime of the Ancient Mariner, the world of positive fact (“It is . . .”) dissolves rather quickly into the shadows of imagination: this is no mere bush, we find out, but one of a mysteriously charged constellation of objects that has taken possession of the speaker’s imagination. He hopes a village tale will supply terms by which he can explain “why” this “spot” should produce such impressive effects out of its simple elements. His initial gesture in this direction is to claim that he “saw” a “woman” at this spot, beside that thorn, crying to herself, “Oh misery! oh misery! / “Oh woe is me! oh misery!”— namely Martha Ray: betrothed, seduced, abandoned in pregnancy on her wedding day, bereaved of her child, and perhaps guilty of infanticide at “the spot.” The interpretive appeal of this rural legend for the speaker is that it plots an objective chain of events that culminate in the affective power of “the spot,” allowing him to displace his obsession with “the spot” to Martha Ray; he is merely an accidetal witness.

But as with the Gloss attached to the Mariner’s “Rime,” here too the very pressures that introduce the cause-and-effect logic of the tale call into question the validity of the proposed explanation. The speaker’s insistence that it was Martha Ray whom he “found,” “saw,” and “heard” “Ere [he] had heard of Martha’s name” may indicate no more than a desperate effort to release his imagination from the grip of a mist-bound panic on a lonely, stormy mountain ridge. Stephen Parrish argues persuasively that the credulous and superstitious speaker may have traced into his account of “the spot” the details of Martha Ray’s history after the event of his own witnessing, converting mere objects into intelligible signs of her ordeal. A psychological urgency shades the explanation promised by the tale into language that expresses the reach for explanation by a mind invaded by mystery. The questioner in the speaker’s audience may plead, “But what’s The Thorn? and what’s the pond? / “And what’s the hill of moss to her?” But that plea, despite its relentless repetition, fails to make the speaker clarify an account suspended uneasily between what he professes to know, or swears is true, and what he “do[es] not know,” “cannot think” or “tell.”

That the poem dramatizes the motions of interpretation as much as it displays the materials of interpretation constitutes what Geoffrey Hartman has, termed the “double plot” of The Thorn, in which “the action narrated and that of the narrator’s mind run parallel.” The question for the speaker is “why?”: what is the connection between the “tale” and “the spot”? But for the reader, that question is compounded with another, about the agent of that second psychological order of action: “What manner of mind is this?” we may ask. Wordsworth himself takes up this last question in his own version of the Coleridgean Argument and Gloss: the long Note he appends to the poem in the second edition of Lyrical Ballads. Addressed to “Readers who are not accustomed to sympathize with men feeling in that manner or using such language,” the Note supplies a sort of second text— that “Introductory Poem” Wordsworth felt he “ought” to have adducced to The Thorn “to give this Poem its full effect.” But unlike Coleridge’s Gloss, Wordsworth’s Note is not concerned with clarifying a principle for the “action narrated”; he means instead to clarify his intent to exhibit what happens to the language of discourse in the absence of such a principle—particularly in the case of a “credulous and talkative” discourser with an imagination “prone to superstition.” Wordsworth argues that the speaker’s particular “manner,” especially his “repetition of words” (a chief complaint among the poem’s first readers), is meant to dramatize an effort “to communicate impassioned feelings”—an effort spurred by “something of an accompanying consciousness of the inadequateness of [his] powers, or the deficiencies of language” to do so.

The speaker’s frustration of plot and his larger struggle with the language of cause and effect thus become a general struggle with all modes of articulation— except the repetition of verbal fragments “which appear successfully to communicate” a feeling, and “the interest” thereby “which the mind attaches to words, not only as symbols of the passion, but as things, active and efficient, which are of themselves part of the passion.” “During such efforts,” Wordsworth explains, “there will be a craving in the mind” which, to the extent that it remains “unsatisfied,” will cause the speaker to “cling to the same words.” Though Coleridge deplored this effect, the circumstances of his own Mariner’s narrative suggest a certain amount of sympathy for its motivation. For the implicit repetition of the Mariner’s “Rime,” and the actual repetitions in The Thorn that play in the voices of both Martha Ray and the ballad’s speaker, all describe motions of mind engaged with what is not too explicit: repetition becomes re-petition, re-asking. As such an interrogative attempt, repetition emerges as another version of the questions that provoke the telling of each tale, that “craving in the mind” for a certainty it cannot locate. Indeed, the voice that actually utters questions in The Thorn is itself a repetitive one. This voice never quarrels with the narrator but merely echoes his tentative discourse in interrogative tones. Both the echoing locution of this voice, as well as its indeterminate origin, suggest that Wordsworth may even be shading the poetics of dialogue into monologue, as if to represent a colloquy within one intelligence, between a voice seeking fact and reason (“But why. . .?”), and a write helplessly burdened with mystery (“I do not know”). The play of these voices, like that between Coleridge’s “Rime” and his framing apparatus, becomes an extended figure for the mind’s engagement with uncertainty. There is a difference, however, for in Wordsworth’s poem the two writes we hear are scarcely distinguishable, and neither presumes interpretive authority.

IV The effort of Wordsworth and Coleridge in these “Lyrical Ballads” to dramatize the uncertainties of interpretation opens a field of rhetorical activity in English Romanticism in which the play of interpretive strategies emerges as a primary subject— a “principle of action” in itself. Shelley writes an ode the whole point of which seems to be to question whether “the human mind’s imaginings” work against a “vacancy” of information in the external world (Mont Blanc); Byron chants playfully: “Apologue, Fable, Poesy, and Parable, / Are false, but may be rendered also true, / By those who sow them in a land that’s arable: / ’T is wonderful what Fable will not do! / ’T is said it makes Reality more bearable” (Don Juan XV:89). Keats’s Odes are perhaps the consummate Romantic instance of a poetic design in which the primary principle of action is a psychological event—a mind exploring and testing its own fictions of interpretation. But narrative, too, becomes arable land for such testing in a poem such as “La Belle Dame Sans Merci,” Keats’s version of a lyrical ballad. As in The Thorn and The Rime of the Ancient Mariner, the central event (the perhaps fatal entanglement of a knight with an enigmatic woman of the meads) emerges only as a troubled memory, the primary action becoming instead the exchange between a perplexed questioner and a would-be tale-teller. The poem opens on an explicitly interrogative note, as a voice arrested by a strange impression queries its cause: “O what can ail thee, knight at arms, / Alone and palely loitering?”

Like the questioners of Wordsworth and Coleridge, Keats’s balladeer seeks a reason for a peculiar phenomenon: what explains this unexpected sight on the meads, a knight absent from his wonted world of quest and romance? What sort of tale awaits the telling? The tone of the question reflects its speaker’s uncertainty, for it suggests at once a moment of puzzled concern for an ailing countryman and a slightly chiding “what-ails-you?” reproach for the appearance of negligence. The description of the landscape that completes the stanza—“The sedge has wither’d from the lake, / And no birds sing”—extends the mood of inquiry by stressing the incongruity of figure and place. Yet there is a gap between the stanza’s questions and its voice of description that raises a question for the reader: are the comments on the landscape a cryptic but potentially meaningful reply to the questioner or a further effort by the questioner to provoke a reply from the knight? That ambiguity, and its mysterious circumstance, persist in the second stanza:

O what can ail thee, knight at arms, So haggard and so woe-begone? The squirrel’s granary is full, And the harvest’s done.

This stanza compounds rather than clarifies the indefinite relation between question and statement, an ambiguity to which I shall return. For now it is enough to note that both the landscape that frames the knight and the statements that frame the questions announce a world of depleted vitality, no longer productive of any harvest, even, apparently, the harvest of inquiry: the field is unyielding for all. The principle of inaction seems the profoundest absence of all; indeed, the questioning voice is the singular movement in this otherwise barren circumstance.

The adjectives “haggard” and “woe-begone” (as well as the previous stanza’s “Alone” and “loi- tering”) begin to play against this vacancy of information, however, by hinting at anterior events: “woe-begone” and “Alone” suggest diagnoses of an ailment for which “loitering” may be a symptom, while the etymology of “haggard,” along with what Keats might describe as “its original and modern meaning combined and woven together, with all its shades of signification,” suggests an intuition of cause. The modern meaning of “drawn, gaunt, exhausted” is enhanced by the status of “haggard” as an adjective derived from “hag,” implying prior bewitchment. The word points even more specifically to the effects of commerce with a “haggard”: “a wild or intractable female,” and—with special relevance to Keats’s La Belle Dame—with a “‘wild’ expression of the eyes.” May the knight’s present “haggard” appearance be the effect of a contagious encounter with some haggard’s “wild wild eyes”? The latent efforts at interpretation stirring in these adjectives emerge in the overtly symbolic imagery that follows:

I see a lily on thy brow With anguish moist and fever dew, And on thy cheeks a fading rose Fast withereth too.

As Earl Wasserman remarks, this stanza invites a “symbolic reading”: the lily is the harbinger of death (Keats in fact wrote “death’s lilly” in an earlier draft); the “fading rose” (also originally “death’s fading rose”) cannily surmises the fatal fading of romance, while the repetition of the verb “wither” in reference to the knight’s appearance can now suggest an affinity between him and a heretofore incongruous circumstance. The elaboration of detail has begun to resonate with an obscure significance which promises a logical connection: the imagery of the whole reports a hollow center whose very vacancy has become significant. Everything speaks of absences, withdrawals, depletions, and abandonments.

The questioner has in effect entered the realm of latent narrative, for with the cue of this “symbolic reading,” the knight produces a tale whose information confirms all these intuitions and imaginative surmises. Nonetheless, its sequence of events—far from elucidating the original mystery— only deepens its range, for here too details elude definite organization. Wasserman’s study of the poem is particularly alert to “the dim sense of mystery and incompleteness” Keats’s artistry arouses in us, along with the way certain “overtones” in the “affective and image-making energies of the poem” “drive the mind to ask questions of conceptual intent. What, one wonders, is the larger meaning couched in the absence of song? why a knight-at-arms and an elfin grot? and what are the significances of the cold hill side and the pale warriors?” Like the Marginal Editor of the Mariner’s “Rime,” Wasserman means to “penetrate [this] mystery”, and he thinks he has the answer: La Belle Dame “is the ideal” that entices mortal man “towards heaven’s bourne,” but which must elude permanent possession in this world. Other readers surmise different causes and propose “Circe” as a more accurate key to interpretation.

Yet the knight’s tale yields no certain logic either way, for like his questioner, he too is in struggle with indeterminate appearances. “She look’d at me as she did love,” he reports, with a syntax that hovers between a confidently durational sense of “as” as “while” and that of less confident conjecture, “as if.” His subsequent assertion, “And sure in language strange she said—/ I love thee true,” bears no more certainty than the Mariner’s hopefully proffered “Sure my kind saint took pity on me.” In both cases the claim only accentuates the gap between the strangeness of signs and their proposed translations. La Belle Dame escapes logical explication even in retrospect—as the syntax of the knight’s tale everywhere demonstrates: his narration merely accretes from “and” to “and”—a word sounded in fact in every stanza of the ballad, more than two dozen times throughout. As in The Thorn, the final stanza comes to rest on the original mystery, its terms now intensified by the intervening narrative:

And this is why I sojourn here, Alone and palely loitering, Though the sedge is wither’d from the lake, And no birds sing.

Despite the withering of lush romance into a death-pale aftermath, the cause remains unknown. The knight’s summation simply echoes on a syntactic level the absences noted by the questioner. Though he frames an answer in the syntax of explanation (“And this is why. . .”), it is an answer that doesn’t produce much, beyond halting present tenses left wandering between two worlds, one dead and one powerless to be re born. Lacking a clear antecedent, its “this” belies the stress by voice and meter: there is, finally, no “why” to solve the mystery of La Belle Dame or to dispel its lingering effects. Indeed, the knight’s final, haunting repetition of his questioner’s voice only magnifies the interrogative mood of the whole, whose irresolution now involves the reader too.

We should not ascribe that questioning voice simply to ballad convention, however, even if it does perform the conventional service of prompting a tale. For the very presence of this questioner on the meads is itself questionable. As in The Thorn, the status of the poem’s conversation remains ambiguous enough to suggest two voices playing in one intelligence, instead of two dramatically distinct speakers. We note, for instance, a curiously shared attraction to the landscape of barren meads, as well as a shared song—the knight reports being spellbound by “La Belle Dame sans Merci,” and the balladeer repeats the spell of that language strange in the title of his own song. Keats enhances these provocative affinities by keeping the identity of the questioner anonymous (more a voice than a character) and by withholding any punctuation that might distinguish two separate speakers. There is a quality to the place and play of these voices, in other words, that implies the self-questioning motions of a divided consciousness examining its forlorn state. Even the knight’s summary statement, “And I awoke and found me here,” points to selfdivision and the need to heal it, with the location of “here” suspended between a situation in the landscape and a situation in the mind. Like The Thorn, Keats’s lyrical ballad allows a reading of its voices as a dialogue of the mind with itself; by the end of the poem, the question that drew our attention to the knight has been utterly absorbed into his own voice. The status of the ballad’s dialogue must of course remain part of its mystery—neither clearly an internal colloquy nor a conversation between distinct dramatis personae. But the ambiguity is suggestive, for it points toward the rhetorical play of the odes, which, as many readers remark, is one of internal dialogue and debate.

V If “La Belle Dame sans Merci” foregrounds a probing question and a perplexed reply against a set of events that haunt about the shape of present speech, “Ode on a Grecian Urn” heightens that drama of interpretation. Instead of a narrative organization of tale, tale-teller, and listener (or reader), Keats concentrates the action of the poem on the motions of a single lyric intelligence engaged with an image: a tableau on an urn, which like “the spot” in The Thorn or the appearance of the knight on the meads seems to signify something beyond itself, but for which there is no “legend” forthcoming, problematic or not. Keats’s field of action is that of a poet’s mind beckoned to interpretation, and the drama he presents concerns the increasingly self-conscious attempts of that mind to describe the significance of the object before it.

Like “La Belle Dame,” the Ode begins with a greeting that suggests there is a story to be told, a meaning to be expressed:

Thou still unravish’d bride of quietness, Thou foster-child of silence and slow time, Sylvan historian, who canst thus express A flowery tale more sweetly than our rhyme.

All the vocatives—an “unravish’d bride,” a “foster-child,” a silent tale-teller—suggest an unfinished circumstance—or from a rhetorical point of view, information on the verge of expression. Keats brilliantly exploits that implication by following these invocations with a series of questions, the syntactic equivalent of these figures of provocative incompletion:

What leaf-fring’d legend haunts about thy shape Of deities or mortals, or of both, In Tempe or the dales of Arcady? What men or gods are these? What maidens loth? What mad pursuit? What struggle to escape? What pipes and timbrels? What wild ecstasy?

If the speaker surmises the urn as a silent Grecian “historian,” the questioning of his “rhyme” provides a particularly cooperative voice, for historia is the Grecian method of learning by inquiry. Yet the attempt to double the historians on this occasion produces an ironic counterplay in the language of poetic inquiry. Far from recovering the mysterious legend presumably harbored by this “Sylvan historian,” the speaker’s rhyme doubles back on itself to mirror his own perplexities: he barely launches his greeting before it branches into multiple “or”s, a kind of “wild ecstasy” of syntax that diagrams his “mad pursuit” of his own “maiden loth”—the unravished “what” that might supply the absent meaning of the images he riddles. As Keats’s speaker pursues the significance of his object, Keats’s rhyme mirrors the course of that pursuit.

Keats’s Ode continues to elaborate this double plot, presenting a speaker in pursuit of interpretation in rhyme that expresses, primarily, the ardor of the pursuer. If, however, Keats’s readers are inclined to exempt themselves from this mirror-play, they have unwittingly played into an even more subtle irony. For over the course of the Ode, Keats turns the behavior of his rhyme into a dilemma for the reader, fully analogous to the speaker’s dilemma of interpretation before the urn. By the conclusion of the Ode, in fact, the reader may have the uneasy feeling that not only have these dilem- mas converged, they may even have reversed, for Keats’s speaker abandons us with an ambiguously toned “that is all” just before becoming as silent as the urn itself.

The dovetailing of the two dilemmas of interpretation— the speaker’s of the urn and the reader’s of the rhyme—begins as soon as the speaker stops questioning to muse on the freedom of the urn from any finite significance. If no “legend” can be read into the silent tableau, it may be because “Heard melodies are sweet, but those unheard / Are sweeter.” With this new premise, the absent “legend” finds a productive counterpart in “unheard” melodies, those “ditties of no tone” played “Not to the sensual ear, but, more endear’d . . . to the spirit.” The language of Keats’s poetry intensifies that paradox with a play of visual repetitions and halfheard echoes. The word “ear,” for instance, reemerges enfolded in “endear’d,” as if that repetition were both a visual and auditory figure for the inner audience to which it refers. Furthermore, the sound (as well as the spelling) of “endear’d” resonates as “end ear’d,” as if to signify audience beyond the bourn of “the sensual ear”—“just below the threshold of normal sound,” as Cleanth Brooks puts it. The slant and sight rhyme of “endear’d” with “unheard” adds a further elaboration to the visual and auditory design of rhyme. As readers, we begin to attend to information that haunts about the shape of rhyme, as well as the information it expresses through the logic of paradox. Language itself becomes a provocative figure of nterpretation.

Yet that very elaboration of linguistic surface further perplexes these “ditties of no tone,” for the speaker has a tone, or rather tones, that correspond ambivalently to the absences he notes:

Fair youth, beneath the trees, thou canst not leave Thy song, nor ever can those trees be bare; Bold lover, never, never canst thou kiss, Though winning near the goal—yet, do not grieve; She cannot fade, though thou hast not thy bliss, For ever wilt thou love, and she be fair!

Any effort to evaluate the syntax of these judgments is thoroughly involved with the speaker’s own perplexity before the arrested figures he contemplates. On the one hand, “Fair youth” and “Bold lover” present ideal images of mortals whose special stasis insulates them from the normal attritions of human passion and the vagaries of human inspiration; “the negation of these verbs,” Earl Wasserman insists, “creates an infinity of mutable or chronological time.” But the dependency of surmise on such negatives may be decreative as well, for the tone of the whole is poised between emphatic celebration and rueful irony: “do not grieve; / She cannot fade.” The initially bold assurance of “therefore, ye soft pipes, play on” succumbs to the wavering balance of “Though . . . yet . . . though,” while the expansive potential of figures seemingly poised on the verge of action yields figures trapped in an eternity of postponements.

The third stanza heightens these tensions of interpretation, both for the speaker and for us, not with syntactic equivocation this time, but with a univocal insistence on gradations of happiness, where the very repetition of positive value exposes the urgency with which it is being declared:

Ah, happy, happy boughs! that cannot shed Your leaves, nor ever bid the spring adieu; And, happy melodist, unwearied, For ever piping songs for ever new; More happy love! more happy, happy love! For ever warm and still to be enjoy’d . . .

Like the repetitions of Wordsworth’s Sea Captain in The Thorn, here too “words” verge on becoming mere “things” of passionate speech, rather than “symbols:” They render a linguistic event that like the branching syntax of stanza 1 or the seesawing sentences of stanza 2 aligns the reader of Keats’s “rhyme” ever more sharply with the interpretive dilemma of the beholder before the urn.

This third stanza concludes with a particularly intense convergence of situation and syntax that invariably trips Keats’s readers:

For ever panting, and for ever young; All breathing human passion far above, That leaves a heart high-sorrowful and cloy’d, A burning forehead, and a parching tongue.

On a first reading, “All breathing human passion far above” seems to be a summary phrase for the state of “More happy love! . . . For ever panting, and for ever young”: the semicolon after “young” perhaps marks a pause analogous to a comma, like the semicolons after “adieu” and “new” in the same stanza, while, conversely, the comma after “above” temporarily halts our reading in this field of happy surmise. Moreover, the stanza’s syntax encourages us to feel that there is no problem in reading “breathing” as a continuation of those activities that the speaker has also described in present participles, “piping” and “panting”—activities that in fact involve kinds of “breathing.” Wasserman puts the case this way: the line “is the syntactical analogue” of a visionary ideal where “breathing human passion” exists in a state “far above,” fusing “mortal and immortal, the temporal and the atemporal.” We may even be inclined to read “All” as an inclusive noun for the melodist and the lovers, and “breathing” as a verb whose direct object is “human passion.”

The comma keeps us reading, however, and as we do, we reject this last syntactic possibility. More important, we find that “far above” is not a place but a value judgment that separates “All breathing human passion” from the conditions of the “happy love” we have been imagining. The value of “breathing” does perplex that judgment with information that will emerge more fully in stanza 5’s “Cold Pastoral!”—an obverse evaluation of the same condition. But at this point, “breathing” is realigned only with the “sorrowful” conditions of the immediately ensuing participles, “burning” and “parching,” its situation distilled utterly from the possibility of mystical convergence with “for ever panting and for ever young.”

What is striking about this line, and the stanza as a whole, is the “phenomenology of reading” it produces. The teetering syntax of “All breathing human passion far above”—first promoting, then subverting, a coordination between the “happy love” on the urn and the highest promise of “human passion”—becomes significant not only for what it would describe, but for the way it behaves. Just as the urn’s art resists decisive interpretation, so that one line entangles nearly every reader who has studied Keats’s Ode. The question of narrative legend (“What men or gods are these?”) moves, in this stanza, into a question of grammar and syntax: “What nouns or verbs are these?” Ambiguity is now the common property of urn and rhyme, and the dilemma of interpretation, the common situation of Keats’s speaker and Keats’s reader.

The return of questions in stanza 4 can be only an ironic event after these doublings of dubious surmise. They seem deliberately calculated to demonstrate the futility of certain interpretation:

Who are these coming to the sacrifice? To what green altar, O mysterious priest, Lead’st thou that heifer lowing at the skies, And all her silken flanks with garlands drest?

This object of address is not the potentially intelligent “Sylvan historian” of stanza 1 but a “mysterious priest,” whose knowledge (like his identity) is beyond possible knowing. Nor is there any possibility of discerning a historical context for this “sacrifice”: origin and termination can be a matter of surmise only:

What little town by river or sea shore, Or mountain-built with peaceful citadel, Is emptied of this folk, this pious morn?

The question of “what little town” echoes the earlier inquiry for “what leaf-fring’d legend,” but here the configuration of “or”s concerns one of those “Nothings” that have existence only in the “ardent pursuit” of imagination. The circumstance is without a representation and, significantly, without a voice:

And, little town, thy streets for evermore Will silent be; and not a soul to tell Why thou art desolate, can e’er return.

The connective “And” hardly breaks the flow of the question, for it produces a response that extends interrogative motion into an undoing of its very premises. In stanza 1, the urn as a “bride of quietness” or a “foster-child of silence” suggested a haunting indeterminacy, while the paradox of “unheard melodies” made that “silence” an elusive spiritual extension of sound. Stanza 4 reduces that potential to mere emptiness. Like the landscape in “La Belle Dame” where “no birds sing,” here, too, is a tableau of absence: there is finally no “historian,” “not a soul to tell/Why,” and the voice of bold inquiry, eager to ravish the urn for its “what” and “why,” finds itself ironically partnered to her silence. The final stanza completes this movement: all questions are absorbed by the object that had excited them, and the urn relapses to a mere “Attic shape”—the “attitude” of “silent form” that signals the silencing of inquiry.

Yet even as Keats’s speaker appears to concede this consequence, Keats’s rhyme redeems language by exploiting its multiplicity of interpretive signals. For the profusion of puns and shades of signification that play through the ode’s final stanza at once speak of and enact the indeterminacy the ode has dramatized throughout. If the urn’s art withholds its spectral legend, flattening illusory possibility to a merely opaque “Fair attitude! with brede / Of marble men and maidens overwrought,” Keats takes advantage of the “heard melodies” of poetry to multiply the dimensions of its activity. “Brede,” for instance, describes the quality of the urn’s figured design, but its punning against “breed” and ironic half-echoes of “bride” and “breathe” subtly reject the “human passion” the speaker had projected onto the urn’s fair attitudes. Indeed, “Fair attitude” refers both to the loveliness of the urn’s art and to the fairness, or justice, of its silent seeming. “Overwrought” involves similar shadings, for while it refers to the lapidary quality of the urn’s design, it also criticizes an eternity where one may never, never kiss. And as a pun on over-“raught” (an archaic or Spenserian version of “reached”), it gently mocks the speaker’s previous overreaching to idealize the urn’s tableau, as well as implicates his view of the overwrought figures before him with his own overwrought postures of interpretation—that voice given to chanting, “Ah, happy, happy boughs!. . . More happy love! more happy, happy love!” “I found my Brain so overwrought that I had neither Rhyme nor reason in it— so was obliged to give up,” Keats reports of one mood of composition in the midst of Endymion.

The transition from the “overwrought” brain to “giving up” is in fact the consequence Keats’s final stanza enacts. The resistance of both urn and rhyme to any single pattern of significance is again underscored with the utterance, “Thou, silent form, dost tease us out of thought / As doth eternity: Cold Pastoral!” “Cold Pastoral!” is, of course, the speaker’s decisive revision of his previous surmise, “For ever warm”: the epithet coolly extinguishes the ardor of that pursuit. More important, however, is the way this phrase not only juxtaposes the beholder’s conflicting responses (“Cold” marble, “Pastoral” illusion), but translates that perplexity of signification into a compelling linguistic figure. “Cold Pastoral!” is no reconciliation but rather a tensed collation of opposites: a dynamic, because, unresolvable, oxymoron. The disjunctive effect of reading Coleridge’s Marginal Gloss against his Mariner’s “Rime” is something Keats’s “Cold Pastoral” concentrates into a single phrase. It is Coleridge in fact who provides the most cogent Romantic argument for the imaginative value of oxymorons. To defend Shakespeare’s attraction to the figure, he urges allowance for the way oxymoron reveals and perpetuates that

effort of the mind, when it would describe what it cannot satisfy itself with the description of, to reconcile opposites and qualify contradictions, leaving a middle state of mind more strictly appropriate to the imagination than any other, when it is, as it were, hovering between images. As soon as it is fixed on one image, it becomes understanding; but while it is unfixed and wavering between them, attaching itself permanently to none, it is imagination. . . a strong working of the mind, still offering what is still repelled, and again creating what is again rejected.

Not only is this a provocative countertext to Coleridge’s favored poetics of reconciliation, but it is the best reading of “Cold Pastoral” ever not written about the phrase, for it speaks to the way the voice of judgment Keats produces in stanza 5 keeps the mind of the reader working hard in a dialectic of constructions and deconstructions. However teasingly silent this “Sylvan historian” remains about its informing “legend,” it becomes, through the very provocation of its silence, the historian of urn-readers and urn-reading, a historian of the speaker’s activity and our own. The urn befriends its beholders the way Keats’s rhyme does—by encouraging their imaginative activity. We come to value its artistry not so much by what it yields to thought as by what it does to thought—provoking questions and refusing to confirm any sure points and resting places for our reasonings.

The voice of the urn, were one to imagine it, is a perfect contrast to the voice that declares “Cold Pastoral!”: “Beauty is truth, truth beauty” is such a piece of self-enclosed harmony that it merits separation by quotation marks from the rest of the rhyme. Its status is another matter, however. “Beauty is truth, truth beauty” emerges in part as the final, desperate surmise of a beholder not happy with an absent legend, nor with being so teased out of thought, and determined to tease the silent form into oracular utterance. And oracular utterance it seems—a rich, cryptic piece of sententiae antiquae. Yet despite the grace of its neatly balanced syntax, its language proves for some a cold comfort; for the ambiguous situation of this voice compromises its high philosophical tone, bringing a special kind of “woe” to “generations” of readers expecting something more accessible to interpretation. The phrase all but requires another “legend” to help us know what it means. Indeed, the words “Beauty” and “truth” seem so inscrutable as an abstract and brief chronicle of the urn’s art that they sound its “ditties of no tone” with a vengeance. As with the marble brede of figures on the urn’s surface, one may project whatever significance onto the aphorism one wishes: but as with those figures, this phrase contracts to mere opacity if its mystery is too irritably teased.

The statement “Beauty is truth, truth beauty” is a lofty answer that in effect plays ironically against the rhetoric of answering, for it simultaneously invites and repels the possibility of understanding, shaping a piece of “charactered language” that is partly like the “hieroglyphics” Keats celebrates in Kean’s “music of elocution” and partly like the “{hie}ragueglyphics in Moor’s almanack.” The two poles of meaning, “Beauty” and “truth,” slide across their marker of equivalence, “is,” reverse positions at the comma, and so elude syntactic priority that, despite the elegant symmetry of statement, its logic can only be wondered at, like the urn itself. Urn and aphorism together go round and round, each serenely self-enclosed, endlessly circular, resonating with mysterious promise, but “still unravish’d” at last.

The only consequence is a further mockery of the questioner: “—that is all / Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.” This statement, too, has the sound of stable wisdom, but the more one teases it, the more one discovers a tone that unsettles its terms of resolution. That “all” hints at sufficiency, even at mysterious plenitude, and yet it has a ring of dismissal, as if parodying anyone’s effort to “know” “all.” The irony against interpretation is as wry as Robert Frost’s couplet: “We dance round in a ring and suppose, / But the Secret sits in the middle and knows.” For Keats, however, there may be no “Secret”—only the effect of those dancing round and supposing. Whether the speaker imagines “that is all” as the urn’s comment on its aphorism, or himself tells us this, the opacity of the pronoun “that” and the uncertain tone of the whole still leave us wanting to know “what is all?” Keats takes us only this far, then to relinquish us to an utterance that, like the contemplation of eternity, absorbs inquiry into silent thought. Here, a negotiation with “uncertainties, Mysteries, doubts” is not merely an act of mind we observe in another (be it Mariner, Marginal Editor, Sea Captain, knight, or poet), but one that the play of Keats’s language has produced and sustained in the reader’s own experience.

Source: Susan J. Wolfson, “The Language of Interpretation in Romantic Poetry: ‘A Strong Working of the Mind,’” in Romanticism and Language, edited by Arden Reed, Cornell University Press, 1984, pp. 22–49.

Previous

Critical Overview