Emerson and Dewey on Natural Piety
[In the following excerpt, Wilson examines the differences and similarities between the naturalism espoused by Dewey and Ralph Waldo Emerson.]
Today many find themselves to be alienated from a religion with a strong textual tradition and in rebellion against the idea of a transcendent deity. In the nineteenth century, Friedrich Nietzsche said, "it is in one particular interpretation [of distress], the Christian moral one, that nihilism is rooted."1 Rather than simply abandoning religion, some, convinced by Nietzsche's analysis, have sought to combat nihilism by turning to other religious resources. Two American philosophers who have attempted to demonstrate that modern man may yet have a significant religious experience in relation to nature are Ralph Waldo Emerson and John Dewey. Both Emerson and Dewey described forms of naturalism wherein humanity might pursue the ideal ends of their lives in a structured, valuable pattern of practical activity as they interact with nature. It was Dewey who made use of the term "natural piety," but both urged mankind to practice a form of natural piety.2
In this essay, I want to explore the ways that natural piety would be expressed if one adopted the naturalism of Emerson or Dewey. Of course, Emerson was a transcendentalist, Dewey was an instrumentalist. At first glance it may appear that there is only a verbal dispute between Emerson and Dewey regarding the practice of naturalism. The practical reasoning required by both for the practice of natural piety initially appears to be the same. A closer comparison, however, may reveal that the natural piety described by each is fundamentally different. Such a comparison may also demonstrate a methodology for formulating a meaningful response to nihilism. I shall begin with a brief sketch of the naturalism of each author.
I. EMERSON'S VIEW OF NATURE AND NATURAL PIETY
Emerson's view of natural piety emerges from his view of nature. Emerson, who was influenced by Zoroastrianism and Hindu thought, rejected supernaturalism and abandoned Unitarianism in favor of Transcendentalism. He declared his New England transcendentalism to be a form of idealism. In his address to the Masonic Temple in Boston in 1841, "The Transcendentalist," Emerson said, "What is popularly called Transcendentalism among us, is Idealism; Idealism as it appears in 1842. . . . Mind is the only reality, of which men and all other natures are better or worse reflectors."3 Emerson also believed in a form of intuitionism whereby man could become aware of his primordial relation to nature. In his seminal work, Nature, he wrote,
The world proceeds from the same spirit as the body of man. It is a remoter and inferior incarnation of God, a projection of God in the unconscious. But it differs from the body in one important respect. It is not like that, now subjected to the human will. Its serene order is inviolable by us. It is therefore, to us, the present expositor of the divine mind. It is a fixed point whereby we may measure our departure. As we degenerate, the contrast between us and our house is more evident. We are as much strangers in nature, as we are aliens from God.4
Thus, in Emerson's monistic, idealistic view of nature, individuals find themselves to be in direct communion with nature. In this view, one may consciously abet or. suppress one's communion with nature. If one does consciously abet that relationship, one may experience the influx of the divine as a reward for self-reliance. Emerson said, "Revelation is the disclosure of the soul."5 Such a disclosure is described as "an influx of the Divine mind into our mind."6
Emerson's emphasis on self-reliance had a popular appeal among early nineteenth-century North American culture because of the value it attached to independence and its reliance upon natural resources. Yet, Emersonian self-reliance would not produce ungrateful, self-made individuals. Humanity's indebtedness to nature was reaffirmed in Emerson's description of self-reliance, since one's self-reliance was the occasion for the conscious influx of the Divine mind. In his essay "Experience," Emerson said, "Into every intelligence there is a door which is never closed, through which the creator passes."7
I have used the term "natural piety" in connection with Emerson to designate an individual's devotion to nature, that is, one's religious response to nature. For Emerson, this religious response to nature is an outgrowth of one's intuitive grasp of his or her relation to nature. It is not a forced or falsified relationship to nature. In addition, it refers to a state of being in which an individual might become reflectively aware of his or her relation to nature. Let us explore this idea at greater length.
Individuals, who experience themselves as conscious beings, may find themselves alienated from nature. This was a form of insanity, according to Emerson, who said, "The tradesman, the attorney comes out of the din and craft of the street, and sees the sky and the woods, and is a man again."8 The renewal that comes to one who regains a sense of his or her primordial relation to nature in this instance is not the result of some metaphysical transformation. Through a change of one's own conscious perspective one becomes aware of one's metaphysical dependence upon nature. Nature, to which humanity is indebted, stands ever ready to be appreciated. Emerson said, "The simplest person who in his integrity worships God, becomes God; yet for ever and ever the influx of this better and universal self is new and unsearchable."9
The worshiper becomes aware of his or her relation to nature in a state of heightened consciousness. So, does the worshiper arrive at this state of heightened consciousness by artificial inducements? Emerson stressed that this heightened consciousness is not something that the worshiper can force upon himself or herself. Emerson said, "never can any advantage be taken of nature by a trick. The spirit of the world, the great calm presence of the Creator, comes not forth to the sorceries of opium or of wine. The sublime vision comes to the pure and simple soul in a clean and chaste body."10
Only by quietly attuning oneself to nature can an individual enhance his or her relation to nature. One must become insensitive to the hurly-burly lifestyle of the masses so that the voice of nature can be heard. Proximity to natural surroundings may become the occasion for this enhanced awareness of nature, but it is not the cause of that enhanced awareness. Through such simple, natural efforts, one may become aware of a shift of perspective regarding the world. One moves out of a strictly egoistic view to a transcendental view. In a much-cited passage, Emerson said: "In the woods I return to reason and faith. . . . Standing on the bare ground,—my head bathed by the blithe air, and uplifted into infinite space,—all mean egotism vanishes. I become a transparent eye-ball. I am nothing. I see all. The currents of the Universal Being circulate through me; I am part or particle of God."11
In Emerson's view, if individuals were to change their perspective regarding their metaphysical relationship to nature, then a change of perspective would manifest itself in their practical expressions of natural piety. For that reason, intuitionism plays a key role in Emerson's view of humanity's relation to nature. As one turns away from the crowd and the world toward nature, the Oversoul may reveal itself to the listener.
What happens as a result of this experience of worship? First, the worshiper becomes aware of a qualitatively superior relation to nature. Emerson said, "The soul gives itself, alone, original and pure, to the Lonely, Original and Pure, who, on that condition, gladly inhabits, leads and speaks through it."12 So the individual whose life was once plagued by a multitude of competing ends and motivations finds a new sense of integrated purpose and existence. "He will weave no longer a spotted life of shreds and patches, but he will live with a divine unity. He will cease from what is base and frivolous in life and be content with all places and with any service he can render."13
Many of the competing and mutually exclusive finite ends that would otherwise distract an individual would come to be abandoned or reintegrated in a positive way in the life of one who displayed natural piety. Certainly there would be a greater sense of self-confidence in the person displaying natural piety, since the person would learn not to belittle his or her own inner glimmer of truth. Furthermore, a person displaying natural piety might be identifiable as a nonconformist on the strength of his or her self-reliance. As Emerson wrote, "Whoso would be a man, must be a nonconformist. Nothing is at last sacred but the integrity of your own mind. Absolve you to yourself. And you shall have the suffrage of the world."14
Second, adherents to natural piety might also display a different relation to society. On the one hand, they would not enter society as mere conformists. On the other hand, as they entered into social relations, there would be a greater respect for an other because of the recognition of the divine element in the other. Emerson said, "Jove nods to Jove from behind each of us."15 Encountering an other as an embodiment of the divine spirit was certain to influence the social relation that those individuals shared. If the other was not in touch with the divine element in his or her own life, that would limit the possible exchange between the individuals. As Emerson put it, "Everywhere I am hindered of meeting god in my brother, because he has shut his own temple doors and recites fables merely of his brother, or his brother's brother's God."16 Emerson's penetrating insight into human relations led him to condemn slavery openly. He realized that it was a petty-spirited individual who would campaign for world relief for some ethnic group while tolerating the enslavement and victimization of a fellow human within that individual's own community.
Third, if a person were to display natural piety, this would be evident in his or her relation to the surrounding world. That individual would discover that he or she was working in harmony with nature. Likewise, that individual would find that nature was meant to be used for his or her purposes, providing that those were the purposes of nature itself. Emerson realized that much of what passed for prayer within orthodox religious circles was cheap begging. His own view of prayer offers an alternative to that type of practice, while demonstrating how someone displaying natural piety works in cooperation with the world spirit for good:
Prayer that craves a particular commodity, anything less than all good, is vicious. Prayer is the contemplation of the facts of life from the highest point of view. It is the soliloquy of a beholding and jubilant soul. It is the spirit of God pronouncing his works good. But prayer as a means to effect a private end is meanness and theft. It supposes dualism and not unity in nature and consciousness. As soon as the man is at one with God, he will not beg. He will then see prayer in all action. The prayer of the farmer kneeling in his field to weed it, the prayer of the rower kneeling with the stroke of his oar, are true prayers heard throughout nature, though for cheap ends.17
Emerson might be identified as a pantheist.18 The Oversoul or the divine mind is identifiable in all the world. In the case of humanity, the Oversoul is present to inspire the individual, if he or she consciously attended to its prompting. "Idealism sees the world in God. It beholds the whole circle of persons and things, of actions and events, of country and religion, not as painfully accumulated, atom after atom, act after act, in an aged creeping Past, but as one vast picture which God paints on the instant eternity, for the contemplation of the soul. Therefore the soul holds itself off from a too trivial and microscopic study of the universal tablet."19 Natural piety is not only a state of mind but also a state of being that might manifest itself in action as an individual behaved in organic harmony with the leading of nature. The person who is moved to act upon the basis of natural piety is an individualist rather than a conformist.20
II. DEWEY'S VIEW OF NATURE AND NATURAL PIETY
Having examined Emerson's view of nature and natural piety, we are in a better position to understand Dewey's views. Dewey, an instrumentalist, was a firm critic of traditional religion and was committed to an instrumentally valuable form of religiousness that he called natural piety. Most of the observations that I shall make here about Dewey's view of nature and natural piety are drawn from a work he offered in his mature years,A Common Faith.
Throughout the writings of Dewey, one may find an opposition to dualisms, especially the dualisms of classical supernaturalism. Dewey's work A Common Faith is an attempt to show that what is genuinely religious can be emancipated when it is freed of the encumbrances of supernaturalism.21 As we shall see, for Dewey this also meant that the emancipation of the genuinely religious lay in its being freed of metaphysical commitments.
Consider Dewey's comments about mystical experience. Dewey believed that an individual who was committed to supernaturalism had a hermeneutical mind-set that would exploit religious experience for self-validation. Dewey did not deny that one could have a mystical experience, but his criticism was directed against the circular reasoning used to analyze the experience. He wrote, "This dualism as it operates in contemporary interpretation of mystic experience in order to validate certain beliefs is but a reinstatement of the old dualism between the natural and the supernatural, in terms better adapted to the cultural conditions of the present time."22 Dewey thought that a belief in supernatural ism biased our understanding of experience and interfered with our pursuit of ideal ends. "In the degree in which we cease to depend upon belief in the supernatural, selection is enlightened and choice can be made in behalf of ideals whose inherent relations to conditions and consequences are understood. Were the naturalistic foundations and bearings of religion grasped, the religious element in life would emerge from the throes of the crisis of religion."23
Dewey's reactionary comments against supernaturalism are insufficient to determine whether Dewey's naturalism was either pantheistic or atheistic. However, Dewey did not want to have his view of religious experience identified as an atheistic view, because of the pragmatic consequences of that view. Dewey thought that, if the universe were regarded atheistically, it would foster the impression that man's environment is indifferent or hostile to his presence.24 Dewey said, "A religious attitude, however, needs the sense of a connection of man, in the way of both dependence and support, with the enveloping world that the imagination feels is a universe."25 So, Dewey wanted humanity to view the universe as being pragmatically cooperative with humanistic projects, but he did not want to suggest that there was some personal or metaphysical basis for nature's congeniality toward or cooperativeness with humanistic projects.
We may use the term "theistic naturalism" to describe Dewey's viewpoint only if we give a proper account of his use of the term "God." Dewey said, "It is the active relation between ideal and actual to which I would give the name 'God.'"26 He uses the term in a pragmatic sense rather than a strictly metaphysical sense. For instance, "The idea [of God] is, as I have said, one of ideal possibilities unified through imaginative realization and projection. But this idea of God, or of the divine, is also connected with all the natural forces and conditions—including man and human association—that promote the growth of the ideal and that further its realization."27
This usage is consistent with Dewey's instrumentalism, but has generated considerable confusion. Part of the confusion seems to have arisen when Dewey's readers used metaphysical categories to analyze his instrumentalism. Corliss Lamont attempted to alleviate some of this confusion regarding Dewey's metaphysical commitments by corresponding with Dewey. The letters exchanged by Dewey and Lamont for several weeks led Lamont to the following conclusion: "John Dewey was not, then, in any sense a theist, but an uncompromising naturalist or humanist thinker who saw the value of a shared religious faith free from outworn supernaturalism and institutional fanaticism."28
If one is to determine, on the basis of Dewey's usage, the meaning that he attaches to the term "nature," then one needs to appreciate two distinct ways that the term may be used. On the one hand, one may make an undifferentiated use of the term, in which case one does not set nature apart as a conglomerate per se but refers to it as an aggregate. The parts are not taken to be distinguishable from the whole. In a similar vein, one may speak of beings while refraining from speech about Being per se. On the other hand, the term "nature" may also be used to pick out the whole, as such, as opposed to the parts. Something like this happens when ontologists speak of Being per se and juxtapose this term with beings in particular. What usage of the term "nature" do we find in Dewey's writings?
In light of Dewey's special instrumental use of the term "God," I think we are better able to understand his view of nature. Dewey is found to have used the term "nature" in two different senses. Above, Emerson makes use of the term "Nature" in a differentiated sense, so that it is synonymous with God, the Divine mind, and the Oversoul. Dewey is found to have used the term in both a differentiated and a nondifferentiated sense. John Smith observed, "By 'nature' [Dewey] did not mean a cosmic system or order of that sort envisioned by those who adhered to the classical conception of a 'Chain of Being' wherein nature stands as something distinct from man and God .. . at the same time he actually used the classical differential sense when opposing idealists, theists and others bent on denying that the cosmic system exhausts what there is."29
Dewey used the term "nature" in a strictly differentiated sense in his replies to supernaturalists, but these replies were meant to be understood only dialectically. It was suggested above that Dewey's usage of the term "God" was best understood in light of his instrumentalism. It would seem inappropriate to label Dewey a naturalist in the same sense that the label is used for Emerson. Dewey's instrumentalism was opposed not only to dualisms but also to noninstrumentally valuable metaphysical dogmas such as pantheism. A nondifferentiated view of nature is consistent with Dewey's instrumentalism. One might be able to substitute the term "nature" for the term "God" in Dewey's later works, providing that one did not misunderstand the term to be used in some metaphysical or ultimate sense.
For Dewey, natural piety was a way to ennoble individuals and to ally them with the resources of the world so that they might better pursue the ideal ends of a good life, that is, a humanistically good life. Compare the views of Emerson and Dewey regarding the effects of natural piety upon individuals' relations to one another and to society. First, Dewey observed that the particular problems of humanity that the churches of his generation addressed were merely symptoms of a more fundamental problem—the disintegration of the self; and Dewey attempted to show that a holistic solution was needed for this fundamental problem facing humanity. Through the practice of natural piety, one's life became reintegrated with an ideal self, society, and nature: "The self is always directed toward something beyond itself and so its own unification depends upon the idea of the integration of the shifting scenes of the world into that imaginative totality we call the Universe."30 Dewey's point is that, when faced with humanitarian problems, traditional religious practitioners are often standoffish. They refrain from intervening in situations where human welfare is at risk and where their input could contribute to the resolution of the situation. Dewey claimed that "dependence upon an external power is the counterpart of surrender of human endeavor."31 Under the pretense of waiting for divine intervention, followers of traditional religions have too often deliberately refrained from intervening in dire situations.
Emerson held a similar view. He condemned the religious practice of making gratuitous prayers. Emerson held that one's best prayers were the prayers of action, acts done in pursuit of some end. Recall the following quote from Emerson: "The prayer of the farmer kneeling in his field to weed it, the prayer of the rower kneeling with the stroke of his oar, are true prayers heard throughout nature, though for cheap ends."32 Emerson thought that one could interactively communicate with nature through one's behavior rather than by verbal communication. In so doing, one could act for the betterment of one's self.
Second, Dewey's natural piety promoted social intervention rather than supernatural intervention. He wrote, "The old-fashioned ideas of doing something to make the will of God prevail in the world, and of assuming the responsibility of doing the job ourselves, have more to be said for them, logically and practically."33 Dewey did not simply disparage tne laxness of traditional religion in resolving social problems, but he emphasized the value of religiousness for effecting the welfare of mankind. In Dewey's view, not in religion but in religiousness there is "the conviction that, if human desire and endeavor were enlisted in behalf of natural ends, conditions would be bettered."34 In his view, the betterment of the human condition, such as the social relations of humanity, is dependent upon human rather than supernatural intervention.
Third, Emerson and Dewey held very different views on the effect of natural piety upon one's relations to the world. Earlier I discussed how, in Emerson's view, a change of perspectives would follow from reestablishing one's primordial relation with nature. In Emerson's view, that could effectively alienate those quietly attuned to nature from others who were not so attuned. In Dewey's view, no special metaphysical attunement was required, and it is likely that Dewey would have identified that element of Emerson's naturalism as "a romantic idealization of the world." Dewey summarized his view of natural piety as follows: "Natural piety is not of necessity either a fatalistic acquiescence in natural happenings or a romantic idealization of the world. It may rest upon a just sense of nature as the whole of which we are parts, while it also recognizes that we are parts that are marked by intelligence and purpose, having the capacity to strive by their aid to bring conditions into greater consonance with what is humanly desirable."35
HI. PRACTICAL ACTIVITY AND PRACTICAL REASONING
Above, I have attempted to compare the descriptions of natural piety by Emerson and Dewey. The way that practitioners of natural piety would express their faith may be a more pressing consideration. If one were convinced of the value of natural piety how would one implement a program of natural piety? To understand that, we must examine how one moves from faith to practice. Here I give a brief account of how one's faith may be implemented by means of one's practical reason.36 Practical reasoning is goal-directed reasoning that has a performative dimension.
Aristotle understood practical reasoning to be a type of reasoning that issued in practical activity, that is, it was a type of reasoning that had a performative dimension. "Practical wisdom," he claimed, "must be a reasoned and true state of capacity to act with regard to human goods."37 In addition, "understanding and practical wisdom are not the same. For practical wisdom issues commands, since its end is what ought to be done or not to be done; but understanding only judges."38 Understanding is important for making judgments, but one does not necessarily act upon the judgments of one's understanding. In the passage just cited, Aristotle said that understanding "is about the same objects as practical wisdom." Yet, my practical reasoning gives rise to judgments about my personal behavior in a way that my understanding does not. Aristotle said, "'understanding' is applicable to the exercise of the faculty of opinion for the purpose of judging of what some one else says about matters with which practical wisdom is concerned—and judging soundly."39 An individual acts upon the judgments of her own practical reasoning.
Consider a strikingly modern example of practical reasoning found in Aristotle: "If a man knew that light meats are digestible and wholesome, but did not know which sorts of meat are light, he would not produce health, but the man who knows that chicken is wholesome is more likely to produce health."40 In the example, light meats are a healthy type of meat. Yet, much more must be known, if that knowledge is to benefit the conscientious consumer. The consumer must also know what meat tokens are included in this meat type. Poultry and fish could be two meat tokens that would be included in this meat type. Finally, if this knowledge is to be valuable for the individual's health, then the reference to light meat must be extensionally meaningful. To consume a healthy meat, as the example suggests, the individual must be able to identify and procure an available chicken product from the meat market.
Perhaps the best way to examine practical reasoning is to analyze further some of Aristotle's examples. On the one hand, practical reasoning was thought to issue in action. On the other hand, practical reasoning, as Aristotle describes it, was formally similar to classical, syllogistic reasoning. It offers us a logical cross section of action that describes both the origin and end of action. If one acts intentionally, then practical reasoning can demonstrate the origin of that action. Aristotle said, "The origin of action—its efficient, not its final cause—is choice, and that of choice is desire and reasoning with a view to an end." Of course the end of action is the primitive bodily movement intended to precipitate some desirable end. Consider two examples offered by Aristotle:
PS I: 1 should make something good.
A house is something good.
At once I make a house.
PS II: "I have to drink," says appetite.
"Here's a drink," says sense perception.
At once he drinks.41
These examples demonstrate not only the logical progression in practical reasoning, but also the problems associated with it. First, consider how they exemplify practical reasoning. The conclusion of the syllogism is a performative statement reached by a process of reasoning along two lines. One premise is a prescriptive statement of what is desirable.42 The other premise states the means for attaining that desirable end. Of course, the conclusion brings the means and the end together in the form of a plan of action. Douglas Walton said, "Aristotle postulates practical reasoning as a linkage between appetite and sense perception."43
Second, these examples demonstrate some of the problems associated with practical reasoning. Aristotle wrote, "No one deliberates about things that are invariable, nor about things that it is impossible for him to do."44 It seems clear that the efficient cause of choice is both desire and reasoning with a view to an end. G. E. M. Anscombe said, "Aristotle would seem to have held that every action done by a rational agent was capable of having its grounds set forth up to a premise containing a desirability characterisation."45 Such declarative statements of what is desirable, though, prove to be notoriously suspicious. Stating the means for practical reasoning within the intentional plan is doubly problematic. R. M. Hare has argued that we must carefully distinguish between necessary and sufficient conditions for the satisfaction of a practical syllogism.46 For instance, a house may be a good thing, but it can be only a sufficient condition for the satisfaction of the premise that a man must do something good. Furthermore, if the practical syllogism does link sense perception to appetite, then there is an implicit assumption that the judgments of sense perception are warranted. If one were to take action on the basis of a statement of sense perception like "this is water," whether the statement was warranted or unwarranted would be of utmost importance. So, the background beliefs of an actor would play a major role in determining whether that actor was warranted in employing the available means to execute his or her intentional plan.
Practical reasoning is not inevitably doomed to failure. We do routinely engage in practical reasoning, and we do experience a high success rate. The fact that almost all of my audience are not now thirsty is ostensible proof that we are successful at practical reasoning. Nevertheless, I suspect that the practical reasoning required for an agent to perform an act of natural piety is often beset with these problems.
The examples drawn from Aristotle have been used to demonstrate the structure and logical progression employed in practical reasoning. That may now be applied to the naturalism of Emerson and Dewey. I would like to suggest that an actor who displays natural piety has engaged in some form of practical reasoning. I would suggest that the actor has reasoned along the following lines:
PS III: I ought to display natural piety, i.e., to display reverence toward nature.
This is nature.
Therefore, I should display reverence toward this.
Here one should not be misled to believe that this syllogism standardizes expressions of natural piety. Not everyone who displays natural piety will perform the same act tokens, just as not everyone who sets out to do a good thing will construct a house. Suppose that someone said, "I should engage a contract with Sawz Lumber Company to erect a number 34 Williamsburg house." This is a token of a type of behavior, house building behavior. To build a house, one does not merely perform a basic act but engages in an elaborate, intentional plan.47 Likewise, a practitioner of natural piety may adopt an elaborate intentional plan that will make use of act tokens different from those used by another practitioner of natural piety.
IV. COMPARING SOME ENTAILMENTS OF APPLIED NATURAL PIETY
It may appear as if the practical reasoning of a person inspired by Emerson to practice natural piety is indistinguishable from that of a person inspired by Dewey. However, there is a deep-seated difference between the natural piety inspired by Emerson and that inspired by Dewey. To explore this point I shall consider again the three areas where the practice of natural piety manifests itself—in one's self-awareness, in one's social relations, and in one's relations to the environment.
For Emerson and Dewey, the practice of natural piety entails the reintegration of the self. Emerson suggested that we abandon frivolous and mean pursuits when we practice natural piety. Dewey suggested that the otherwise competitive, finite goals that we would pursue are subordinated to a primary, integrating goal—an ideal, imaginary self. Both authors suggest that the person who does not practice some form of natural piety may experience the disintegration of the self. In other words, apart from an expression of natural piety, man may experience himself as someone going in all directions at the same time. Intentional plans formulated for the sake of expressing one's natural piety may counteract the disintegration of the self. From this, one might conclude the following: a necessary condition for all types of natural piety would be the adoption of a self-integrating intentional plan.
The ideal self envisioned by Dewey as an entailment of natural piety could not serve as a substitute for the ideal self envisioned by Emerson. For Dewey, an ideal self is an ideal possibility unified through the imagination. Thus, "God" could influence the formulation of an ideal self, but that would be only an imaginative influence devoid of metaphysical implications. Dewey said, "Suppose for the moment that the word 'God' means the ideal ends that at a given time and place one acknowledges as having authority over his volition and emotion, the values to which one is supremely devoted, as far as these ends, through imagination, take on unity."48 In contrast, Emerson suggested that one obtained a vision of the ideal self under divine inspiration. The metaphysical indebtedness is clear. Emerson said, "within man is the soul of the whole; the wise silence; the universal beauty, to which every part and particle is equally related; the eternal One."49 Given the metaphysical indebtedness of humanity to the Oversoul it is not surprising that such pursuits must be subordinated to the ultimate will of nature. Emerson said, "nature has a higher end, in the production of new individuals, than security, namely ascension, or the passage of the soul into higher forms."50 While Emerson and Dewey both envisioned the reintegration of the self as an entailment of natural piety, their understanding of the nature and emergence of an ideal self differed vastly.
For both Emerson and Dewey, another entailment of natural piety is that one's social relations are enhanced by a sense of dignity, although natural piety does not necessarily drive humanity toward social existence with fellow humans. For Emerson there was a heightened sense of dignity because the practitioner of natural piety recognized the same divine spirit to be in all creatures. Emerson said, "Jove nods to Jove from behind each of us."51 Yet, Emerson attached a negative value to some forms of social existence with fellow humans. Often social existence amounted to nothing more than conformity and herd existence. Emerson stressed that individuals should be related to nature even at the expense of social company. For Dewey individuals carried a heightened sense of dignity to social existence because of their natural piety. Their natural piety liberated individuals from a dependence on otherworldly resources. Thus, individuals developed a newfound sense of dependence upon one another for the achievement of their ideal ends. Rather than driving an individual away from social existence, the natural piety of Dewey turned individuals back to social existence with a newfound zeal for cooperation.
By comparison, Emerson's naturalism might appear to be antisocial, but that would be a misreading of Emerson. According to Emerson the social company that was expendable was infected with insanity, that is, it was mere herd existence that had forsaken its natural heritage. Emerson was quite willing to encourage social relations, provided that the individuals who entered into these relations could reciprocate the spirit of naturalism that he was promoting. While he might have been willing to tolerate other social relations, he found them less than edifying in those instances where the other individual had forsaken or left uncultivated his or her primordial relation to nature.
Perhaps the most evident difference between the natural piety of Emerson and that of Dewey arises in connection with the relation of the individual to the environment. To act reverentially toward nature, one must successfully make the judgment "this is nature." One of two different background beliefs about nature could be held by the practitioner of natural piety. In Emerson's account, nature was described in a differentiated, pantheistic sense; but Dewey's used a nondifferentiated sense of nature. Both recognized the instrumental value of nature, and both urged individuals to make full use of the potential of nature rather than appealing to some otherworldly force. Emerson said, "Nature is thoroughly mediate. It is made to serve. It receives the dominion of man as meekly as the ass on which the Savior rode."52 Yet, we should not overlook the fact that, in Emerson's naturalism, Nature itself had ultimate ends that man was meant to serve. Emerson said that "prayer as a means to effect a private end is meanness and theft. It supposes dualism and not unity in nature and consciousness. As soon as the man is at one with God, he will not beg."53 Dewey could offer his approval of the turn toward nature and away from supernaturalism, but Dewey regarded nature as something instrumentally valuable only. Since the instrumental value of nature was grounded on whatever proved to be instrumentally valuable to humanity, this type of natural piety could justify the displacement of not only ultimate purposes like those envisioned by Emerson but also the purposes of coexistent species. So, the natural piety of Dewey might lead to the exploitation of nature.
It may be enlightening to consider how individuals persuaded by either Emerson or Dewey would react to a current situation, where man's action could place nature at risk. In its July 1994 report to stockholders, one California-based oil and gas company, Unocal, explained its projected expansion program in Southeast Asia.54 Roger Beach, the CEO of the company, emphasized that the company would endeavor both to have a positive impact on local people and to take environmental responsibilities seriously. The expansion program outlined in the report proposes that a natural gas pipeline running through Myanmar to Thailand be installed. The pipeline would cross some rain forest areas. To find out how to minimize environmental damage, the company consulted both a research scientist specializing in rain forests and a tropical botanist. The current plan is to make a minimal clearing for the pipeline and to provide reforestation wherever it is needed. The same research scientist who reviewed the plan said, "there appears to be a way of designing and routing the line to maintain the integrity of the forests."55 While the expansion program will benefit humankind in terms of providing jobs and available energy resources, the proposed plan is also environmentally sensitive in that it promises to minimize the pipeline's environmental impact. The CEO's report was written in response to shareholders who had expressed a concern about humanity's moral obligation to be environmentally sensitive.
One who was persuaded by Emerson to practice natural piety could easily understand the obligation to develop an environmentally sensitive expansion program in this situation. One who was persuaded by Dewey to practice natural piety would not experience the same sense of obligation to act in an environmentally sensitive way. The latter person might reason that, if a plan of action were not more instrumentally valuable for humanitarian ends, it would not be obligatory. In other words, in Dewey's view there is no justification for an obligation ab extra to be environmentally conscientious, whereas in Emerson's view there is. In Dewey's view, environmental conscientiousness would be justified only if it proved to be more instrumentally valuable for humanitarian ends.
V. CONCLUSION
Both Ralph Waldo Emerson and John Dewey included within their naturalism descriptions of natural piety. The person who reflectively reveres nature and who manifests that reverence for nature in practical activity is a practitioner of natural piety. Yet, Emerson and Dewey demonstrated that there may be two vastly different forms of natural piety. Practitioners of both types of natural piety engage in a similar process of practical reasoning, but the practical activity that results differs widely; therefore, through this comparison one finds an apparently verbal dispute that is a genuine dispute. At the heart of the genuine dispute are the different attitudes of Emerson and Dewey toward religion. Emerson's description of natural piety is religious, and the reverence for nature it inspires is metaphysically grounded. Dewey's description of natural piety makes use of an instrumental view of religiousness, and the reverence for nature it inspires is subject to instrumental criteria.
In light of the fact that man resorts to natural piety to combat nihilism, the significance of the latter observation should not be underestimated. Emerson's naturalism would combat nihilism by a return to a metaphysical commitment, whereas Dewey's naturalism would combat nihilism through a plan of action that is fundamentally self-affirmative. Within Emerson's naturalism, individuals travel a path to meaningful existence as they reaffirm their primordial relation to the Oversoul. As they cultivate that relation and allow it to influence all other personal relations, those individuals reclaim for themselves meaningful existence.
Within Dewey's naturalism, to travel a path to meaningful existence one must be disengaged from an otherworldly religious orientation. Then, by focusing upon the potentiality available within nature, one may turn nature toward the service of a humanistically good life. Nature is to be respected for its potentiality and happily engaged in light of its convivial instrumentality, but nature does not become a substitute for some otherworldly deity such that one's efforts are turned toward its service per se. Within Dewey's natural piety, one does not find any justification for Nature worship.
This essay examines two naturalistic solutions to nihilism.56 Nevertheless, there is an important methodological point to be observed here, for anyone attempting to formulate a solution to nihilism. Emerson's description of naturalism is metaphysically grounded, whereas Dewey's description of naturalism is not. Dewey's naturalistic solution to nihilism, without metaphysical grounding, demonstrates how we may resort to self-authenticating tactics to combat meaninglessness. To the extent that these self-authenticating tactics for combating nihilism are environmentally insensitive, they may upon reflection prove to be ultimately self-effacing.
NOTES
1 Friedrich Nietzsche, "The Will to Power," in Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre, ed. Walter Kaufmann (New York: New American Library, 1975), p. 131.
2 John Dewey, A Common Faith (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1934), p. 25.
3 Ralph Waldo Emerson, "The Transcendentalist," in The Complete Essays and Other Writings of Ralph Waldo Emerson (New York: Modern Library, 1940), p. 87.
4Emerson's Nature: Origin, Growth, Meaning, 2d ed., ed. Merton M. Sealts, Jr., and Alfred R. Ferguson (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1979), p. 31. Hereafter, this work shall be cited as Nature. Other references drawn from Emerson's essays shall be cited simply by the name of the essay and the page. References to his essays come from Ralph Waldo Emerson: "Essays and Journals, " selected by Lewis Mumford (Garden City, N.Y.: International Collectors Library, 1968).
5 "Oversoul," p. 204.
6Ibid., p. 203.
7 "Experience," p. 273.
8Nature, p. 11.
9 "Oversoul," p. 208.
10 "The Poet," p. 260.
11Nature, p. 8.
12Ibid., p. 210.
13Ibid., p. 212.
14"Self-Reliance," p. 92.
15"Oversoul," p. 202.
16"Self-Reliance," p. 106.
17Ibid., p. 105.
18 There is some debate whether Emerson should be labeled simply a pantheist or a panentheist. I shall not take up that discussion here. Howeverr I find the possibility that he was a panentheist unlikely, since he took a monistic, idealistic position regarding nature.
19Nature, p. 28.
20 Emerson's description of natural piety is roughly comparable to William James's description of nature mysticism. In Varieties of Religious Experience (New York: New American Library, 1958), James described several incidents where nature awakened within some individual "mystical moods." In a footnote (p. 302) James commented on an incident involving nature mysticism. He said, "The larger God may then swallow up the smaller one." Thus, in James's view, when one encounters the divine element in nature, one may experientially transcend the muffling effect of religious tradition on an encounter with the divine. Recall that Emerson himself found his own religious tradition to be stifling by comparison with his encounter with the Oversoul through nature. James might easily include Emerson within his corps of nature mystics.
21Dewey, p. 2.
22Ibid., p. 38.
23Ibid., p. 57.
24Ibid., p. 53.
25Ibid.
26Ibid., p. 51.
27Ibid., p. 50.
28 Corliss Lamont, "New Light on Dewey's Common Faith," Journal of Philosophy 58, no. 1 (1961): 27.
29 John E. Smith, Purpose and Thought: The Meaning of Pragmatism (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1978), pp. 224-25, n. 86.
30Dewey, p. 19.
31Ibid., p. 46.
32"Self-Reliance," p. 105.
33Dewey, p. 79.
34Ibid., p. 46.
35Ibid., p. 25.
36Above, I explore the way in which one moves from a faith in natural piety to a practice of natural piety. For devotees of natural piety, some of the problems associated with this move from faith to practice may arise as a result of the absence of a firm dogma or revelation in naturalism. More traditional religions rely heavily upon a written or spoken voice of authority to facilitate the move from faith to practice. Nevertheless, I suspect that practitioners of more traditional forms of religion are not exempt from some of the same difficulties associated with the move from faith to practice through practical reasoning, and I hope to explore that idea in an upcoming project.
37The Works of Aristotle, ed. J. A. Smith and W. D. Ross, vol. 5 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1912), Nicomachean Ethics, 1140b20; hereafter cited as Aristotle, NE.
38Ibid., NE 1143a8.
39Ibid., NE 1143a 13-15.
40Ibid., NE 1141b18.
41Here I give Walton's modernized rendition of Aristotle's syllogisms. See Douglas Walton, Practical Reasoning: Goal-Driven, Knowledge Based, Action-Guiding Argumentation (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1990), p. 11. Aristotle said, "For the actualization of desire is a substitute for inquiry or reflection. I want to drink, says appetite; this is drink, says sense or imagination or mind: straightaway I drink. In this way living creatures are impelled to move and to act, and desire is the last or immediate cause of movement, and desire arises after perception or after imagination and conception" (see Aristotle, NE 701a30-40; PS = Practical Syllogism).
42Some further work has been done on the analysis of practical reasoning by Michael Bratman. In his book, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1987), Bratman suggested that practical reasoning occurred on two levels. He said, "Prior intentions and plans pose problems and provide a filter on options that are potential solutions to those problems; desire-belief reasons enter as considerations to be weighted in deliberating between relevant and admissible options" (p. 35). The prescriptive statement of what is desirable could be correlated with Bratman's first level of practical reasoning. One develops an intentional plan that designates some desirable end as its goal.
43Walton, p. 11.
44 Aristotle, NE 1140a33.
45 G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (New York: Cornell University Press, 1963), p. 72.
46 R. M. Hare, Practical Inferences (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1972), p. 60.
47 See n. 34 above. If we were to make use of Bratman's analysis of practical reasoning here, we could say that the decision to build a particular house took place on the second level of practical reasoning. At that level, one could develop a subplan that included all the specific details of the contract with Sawz Lumber Company. Thus, the performance of basic acts would be understood to take place within an elaborately structured plan that would also include specific subplans such as the one described in the text.
48 Dewey, p. 42.
49 "Oversoul," p. 197.
50 "The Poet," p. 258.
51 'Oversoul," p. 202.
52Nature, p. 20.
53 "Self-Reliance," p. 105.
54 "Unocal in Myanmar: Report to the Stockholders" (Los Angeles, Calif., Corporate Communications Department, Unocal Corp., 1994).
55Ibid., p. 7.
56 I myself am inclined to believe that an effective way to combat nihilism lies along a path similar to the one taken by Emerson though significantly different. To me it seems that the panentheistic solution to the problem that has been described by Charles Hartshorne and has been developed within process theism by thinkers like Schubert Ogden and John B. Cobb may be an effective way to combat nihilism. I leave the discussion of that line of thought to be developed elsewhere.
Get Ahead with eNotes
Start your 48-hour free trial to access everything you need to rise to the top of the class. Enjoy expert answers and study guides ad-free and take your learning to the next level.
Already a member? Log in here.
Sport, the Aesthetic, and Narrative
Desire and Desirability: A Rejoinder to a Posthumous Reply by John Dewey