(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Broadly speaking, theories in the philosophy of mind are of two sorts: dualist and materialist. Dualist theories, such as the one associated with French philospher René Descartes, claim that there are two fundamentally different kinds of substances in the world: physical substances such as the body and mental substances such as the mind. In contrast, materialist theories claim that there are only physical substances; hence, on a materialist view, mental states are standardly understood to be physical states of the brain.

Patricia Smith Churchland falls squarely in the materialist camp, believing that the mind should be identified with the brain. In fact, she approaches her study in terms of neither the “mind” nor the “brain” but rather in terms of the “mind-brain.” As its subtitle suggests, Neurophilosophy lays the groundwork for a theory of the mind-brain and, according to Churchland, this theory must be informed not only by philosophical work but also by neuroscientific research. Toward this end, Churchland’s primary aim in the book is to bridge the gap between neuroscience and philosophy, acquainting researchers in these fields with one another.

Neurophilosophy Rejection of Folk Psychology

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

In this way, Churchland assigns to philosophers an important role in the development of a theory of the mind-brain, but it is important to note that she does not think that the needed philosophical work can be done from the armchair, so to speak. Churchland argues persuasively that an adequate theory of the mind must be informed by empirical research. She thus calls for the rejection of what is usually referred to as “folk psychology,” our commonsense understanding of mental states and processes.

Folk psychology consists of a vast network of rough generalizations, usually invoking propositional attitudes such as beliefs and desires, that explain behavior. For example, two such generalizations are as follows: (1) When a person desires to bring about some state of affairs S and believes that her doing action A is the best way to bring about S, then (other things being equal) she will do A; (2) When a person desires to prevent some state of affairs S and believes that S will result from her doing action A, then (other things being equal) she will refrain from doing A. Philosophers of mind have generally assumed that any adequate theory of the mind must, to at least a significant extent, respect the generalizations of folk psychology and account for the propositional attitudes it posits. Churchland thinks that this assumption is deeply mistaken. Advances in physics came only when...

(The entire section is 525 words.)

Neurophilosophy Search for a Theory of Neuroscience

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Having surveyed the neuroscientific and the philosophic terrain in parts 1 and 2, respectively, in the final part of Neurophilosophy Churchland attempts to survey the theoretical terrain. As she notes, though neuroscientists know a significant amount about the structure of nervous systems, they lack a theoretical framework in which to make sense of their experimental results. Against the claims of many neuroscientific researchers that it is still too early for theorizing, or that theorizing is too abstract, Churchland argues that the organizational and motivational value of theories should not be underestimated. Though much of her book seems to be directed toward philosophers, attempting to convince them of the importance of neuroscience, the opening section of part 3 seems clearly aimed at neuroscientists, attempting to convince them of the importance of philosophy.

According to Churchland, the search for a theory should be guided by the following question: What sort of organization in neuronlike structures could produce the output in question (motor control, visual perception, memory, and so on), given the specified input? An ideal theory, or proto-theory, will have what she calls a “Galilean combination” of simplification, unification, and mathematization. Churchland does not herself offer such a theory, but rather, in the remainder of the book, surveys three theoretical ventures in an attempt to show what shape a unified theory of the mind-brain might take.

The tensor network theory, the first theory that Churchland presents and the one to which she devotes the most attention, targets the problem of sensorimotor control by providing a general framework for understanding the computational architecture of nervous systems. In an attempt to make this very complicated theory...

(The entire section is 739 words.)

Neurophilosophy Bibliography

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Additional Reading

Bechtel, William. “Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind: An Overview.” In Mind and Cognition, edited by William Lycan. Oxford, England: Blackwell, 1990. Bechtel provides a useful, general survey of some of the philosophical issues surrounding connectionism, the theory of the mind that Churchland puts forward in both Neurophilosophy and The Computational Brain.

Campbell, Keith, et al. “Commentaries on Neurophilosophy.” Inquiry 29 (1986). In a special issue devoted to a symposium on Churchland’s book Neurophilosophy, six commentaries are followed by replies from Churchland.

Churchland, Patricia Smith. “Take It Apart and See How It Runs.” In Speaking Minds: Interviews with Twenty Eminent Cognitive Scientists, edited by Peter Baumgartner and Sabine Payr. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995. This interview finds Churchland discussing her approach to philosophy, how she initially became interested in neuroscience, and her views on the discipline of cognitive science. The volume also contains an interview with Churchland’s husband, Paul, entitled “Neural Networks and Commonsense.”

McCauley, Robert N., ed. The Churchlands and Their Critics. Oxford, England: Blackwell, 1996. The first half of this anthology contains nine essays on the works of both Patricia and Paul Churchland. The contributors come from a wide variety of fields, such as philosophy, neurology, neuroanatomy, and psychology. In the second half of the anthology, the Churchlands jointly respond to their critics. Their responses proceed thematically, covering five major topics: the future of psychology (both folk and scientific), the impact of neural network models on the philosophy of science, semantics in a new vein, consciousness and methodology, and moral psychology and the rebirth of moral theory. Suitable for advanced students.

Stich, Stephen. From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1983. The argument that Stich launches against folk psychology makes many points of contact with Churchland’s work. Especially relevant is chapter 10.