(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

The Glorious Revolution of 1688 saw the expulsion of James II from the throne of England and the triumph of Whig principles of government. James had been accused of abandoning the throne and thus violating the original contract between himself and his people. Two years later, John Locke’s Of Civil Government: The Second Treatise appeared in Two Treatises of Government and was looked upon by many as a tract that justified in philosophical terms those historical events. The first treatise had been an argument against the view that kings derive their right to rule from divine command, a view held by England’s royal family the Stuarts, especially James I, and defended with no little skill by Sir Robert Filmer in his Patriarcha (1680).

After rejecting Filmer’s thesis, Locke looked for a new basis of government and a new source of political power. He recognized that the state must have the power to regulate and preserve property, and that to do so it must also have the right to punish, to use the death penalty and all lesser ones. In order to carry out the laws passed, the force of the community must be available to the government, and it must also be ready to serve in the community’s defense from foreign injury. Political power by which the government performs these functions ought to be used only for the public good and not for private gain or advantage. Locke then set out to establish a basis for this power, a basis that he considered moral and just.

Of Civil Government Natural Law as the Basis of Government

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

He turned to a concept used by political theorists since the time of the Stoics in ancient Greece: natural law with its concomitants, the state of nature and the state of war. Many philosophers have objected to the state of nature as a concept because history does not indicate that such a state existed. In Of Civil Government Locke tries to answer this objection by pointing to “primitive” societies known in his day, the nations of Indians living in the New World. However, that was not a strong argument and was not really needed by Locke. The concept of the state of nature can be used as a device to set off and point up the difference between a civil state in which laws are enacted by the government and a contrasting state in which either these laws are absent in principle or another set of laws prevails. In this way, the basis of civil enactments and the position of the individual within society may be better understood.

This applies also to the other concepts mentioned, the state of war and natural law. At any rate, Locke holds that in the state of nature one may order one’s own life as one sees fit, free from any restrictions that other people might impose; in this sense, each individual and all others are equal. They are equal in a more profound sense from which, as it were, their right to act as independent agents comes; that is, as children of God. By use of reason, people can discover God’s commands by which they should order their lives in the state of nature. These commands are called the “laws of nature.” Thus, although one is free to act as one pleases in the state of nature, one is still obligated to act according to God’s commands. This ensures that one’s actions, although free, will not be licentious. The basic restriction that God’s laws place on an individual is that one treat others as one would like to be treated. Because people are equal and independent, they should not harm one another regarding their “life, health, liberty, or possessions.”

Of Civil Government Free Will

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Humanity’s glory as well as its downfall has been free will, whereby one may choose to do or not to do what one ought to do. To preserve oneself from those who choose to inflict harm, one has the right to punish transgressors of the law. Reparation and restraint are the two reasons that justify punishment when one by one’s acts has shown that one has agreed to live by a law other than that which common reason and equity dictate; that is, one has chosen to violate God’s orders. The right to punish is thus a natural right by which people in the state of nature may preserve themselves and humankind from the transgressions of the lawless. This right is the basis for the right of governments to punish lawbreakers within the state; thus, Locke provides a ground for one aspect of political power that he had noted earlier.

Of Civil Government The State of War

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

When an individual indicates through a series of acts that are apparently premeditated that he or she has designs on another’s life or property, then that person enters into a state of war, a state of enmity and destruction, toward the intended victim. In the state of nature, people ought to live according to reason and, hence, according to God’s commands. Each individual must be the judge of his or her own actions, for on earth there is no common superior with authority to judge between that person and another when a question of aggression arises and when relief is sought. One’s conscience must be one’s guide as to whether one is in a state of war with another person.

In the Declaration of Independence, the American colonists proclaimed that people had natural rights granted to them by their Creator and that governments were instituted by people with their consent to protect these rights. Locke, as pointed out, held these rights to be life, liberty, and property, whereas the Declaration proclaims them to be life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. It is interesting that Thomas Jefferson, the author of the Declaration of Independence, pondered whether to use “property” or “pursuit of happiness” and in an early draft actually had written the former. Much of Locke’s discussion in On Civil Government influenced the statesmen and leaders of the colonies during the period of the American Revolution.

Of Civil Government Property

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Locke seems to use various senses of “property” in his discussions. Speaking quite generally, one might say that whatever was properly one’s own—whatever God had endowed an individual with or whatever the legislature of the commonwealth had declared as legal possession—no one else had a claim to. In spelling out this idea, Locke starts first with one’s own body, which is God-given and which no one has a claim upon; an individual has a right to be secure in his or her person. Included in this idea is the fact that life itself is a gift to which no one else has a claim, as well as the freedom to move about without restriction.

There is next the more common use of “property,” which is often rendered “estate” and which refers to the proper possessions that one gains in working the earth that God has given people to use for the advantage of their lives and their convenience. Because working for one’s own advantage and convenience involves the pursuit of happiness, it can be seen in what way the terms “property” and “pursuit of happiness” are interchangeable. This more common use of “property” is, nonetheless, related to the first use in Locke’s theory. What is properly a person’s own may be extended when, with regard to the common property that God has blessed people with for their use, a person mixes labor with it and makes it his or her own. Divine command prescribes, however, that one take no more than one needs, for to...

(The entire section is 440 words.)

Of Civil Government The Case for Government

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Locke has shown that although people ought to live according to divine commands, some do not and thus turn the state of nature into one of war. Because there is no common superior on earth to whom one can turn for restitution, people are often left helpless. It is obvious that not every injury imagined is a wrong, that two individuals in conscience may disagree, and that those instances of obvious wrongs are not always rectifiable when people have only their own judgments and strength to depend upon. A disinterested judge, supported by more power than a single person has alone, may provide people with a remedy for the insecurity that exists in the state of nature. In the most general sense of “property,” a commonwealth may provide the solution to its preservation and security by making public the laws by which people ought to live, by establishing a government by which differences may be settled through the office of known and impartial judges who are authorized to do so, and by instituting a police force to execute the law, a protection absent in the state of nature. People give up their rights to judge for themselves and to execute the laws of nature to the commonwealth, which in turn is obligated to use the power that it has gained for the ends that led to the transference of these rights. In giving up their rights, people consent to form a body politic under one government and, in so doing, obligate themselves to every member of that society to submit to the...

(The entire section is 594 words.)

Of Civil Government Obligations of Government

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

There are certain aspects of government that Locke believed must be maintained to ensure that it functions for the public good:1. The legislative, which is the supreme governmental power, must not use its power arbitrarily over the lives and fortunes of the people. The law of nature still prevails in the governments of humankind. 2. Nor should power be exercised without deliberation. Extempore acts would place the people in as great jeopardy as they were in the state of nature. 3. The supreme power cannot take property from a person without that individual’s consent. This principle applies also to taxation. 4. The legislative power cannot be transferred to anyone else, but must remain in the hands of that group to which it was...

(The entire section is 141 words.)

Of Civil Government Separation of Powers

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Locke believed that the interests of the people would be protected more fully in a government in which the three basic powers—legislative, executive, and federative—were separate and distinct in their functions. The legislature need meet only periodically, but the executive should be in session continually, whereas the management of the security of the commonwealth from foreign injury would reside in the body politic as a whole. Strictly speaking, the federative power—treaty making and so forth—need not be distinguished from the legislative. It is interesting that the three branches of government in the United States include the judiciary rather than the federative, which is shared by both the executive and legislative...

(The entire section is 266 words.)

Of Civil Government Violation of the Social Contract

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

When a government exercises power beyond right, when public power is used for private gain, then tyranny prevails. Such acts set the stage for the dissolution of government. It should be pointed out that in forming a community and in delegating power to a government, the people, especially in the latter case, enter into an agreement or, analogously, into a social contract with their government to provide them with security, preservation, and those conveniences that they desire, in exchange for the transference of their rights and the honor, respect, and obligation that they render to the government. The violation of their part of the contract leads the government to declare them (as individuals) outlaws, to use its police force to...

(The entire section is 396 words.)

Of Civil Government Bibliography

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Additional Reading

Ayers, Michael. Locke. New York: Routledge, 1999. An excellent biographical introduction to the thoughts of the philosopher, clearly presented and requiring no special background. Bibliography.

Brantley, Richard E. Locke, Wesley, and the Method of English Romanticism. Gainesville: University of Florida Press, 1984. Brantley alleges that John Locke influenced John Wesley, the founder of the Methodist Church, and that Wesley’s work influenced the eighteenth century Romantic poets.

Chappell, Vere, ed. John Locke: Theory of Knowledge. New York: Garland, 1992....

(The entire section is 371 words.)