Arthur Schopenhauer Biography

Bibliography (Critical Survey of Ethics and Literature)

Atwell, John E. Schopenhauer on the Character of the World: The Metaphysics of Will. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995. Atwell’s extended analysis of The World as Will and Idea attempts, against the views of others, to establish that Arthur Schopenhauer has a metaphysics, though a severely limited one.

Atwell, John E. Schopenhauer: The Human Character. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1990. In a topical, highly readable approach, Atwell explores Schopenhauer’s ethics. Like other critics, he presses Schopenhauer’s examples logically to the point that they break down and reveal contradictions.

Fox, Michael, ed. Schopenhauer: His Philosophical Achievement. Brighton, England: Harvester Press, 1980. A collection of essays by distinguished scholars. The book is divided into three sections: general articles, giving overviews of Schopenhauer; articles dealing with basic philosophical issues; and comparative studies that relate Schopenhauer’s philosophy to others’ and explore intellectual debts.

Gardiner, Patrick L. Schopenhauer. Bristol, England: Thoemmes Press, 1997. A piercing analysis of Schopenhauer’s life and philosophy.

Hamlyn, D. W. Schopenhauer. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980. A general survey of Schopenhauer’s philosophy. Clarifies his terms, explains his epistemology, and offers extensive analysis of his philosophical debt to Kant.

Jacquette, Dale, ed. Schopenhauer, Philosophy, and the Arts. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996. A penetrating look at Schopenhauer’s philosophy and aesthetics.

Janaway, Christopher. Schopenhauer. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, 1994. Janaway’s concise though dense overview of Schopenhauer’s life and philosophical system represents an excellent introduction. Synopses of the major works are supplemented by references to lesser-known titles. Janaway exposes some limitations and contradictions in Schopenhauer’s system, notably in his concepts of will, freedom, ethics, and pessimism.

Safranski, Rüdiger. Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990. Essentially a biography, the book recounts the life and works of Schopenhauer. Safranski suggests that events in Schopenhauer’s life contributed to his outlook and the formation of his pessimistic system. In addition, he places the philosophy within the aesthetic and intellectual currents of Schopenhauer’s time. For a review of this biography see Magill’s Literary Annual review.

Tanner, Michael. Schopenhauer. New York: Routledge, 1999. An excellent biographical introduction to the thoughts of the philosopher, clearly presented and requiring no special background. Includes bibliography.

Arthur Schopenhauer Biography (Critical Survey of Ethics and Literature)

0111206086-Schopenhauer.jpgArthur Schopenhauer (Library of Congress) Published by Salem Press, Inc.

Financial independence enabled Schopenhauer to devote his life to philosophy, and he developed his pessimistic system as a follower of Immanuel Kant. In The World as Will and Idea, he identifies the will as the Kantian thing-in-itself that comprehends the external world through the mental constructs of time, space, and causality. As Schopenhauer understood it, will comprises intellect, personality, and the potential for growth and development. Although powerful, it is not free but is controlled by causation like all else that exists. Confronting a meaningless existence and a godless universe, Schopenhauer concluded that ethical behavior requires withdrawal from the pleasures of life in favor of contemplation. The individual must tame the will so that it becomes less insistent on its egoistic desires, which lead only to further desires. Where others are concerned, the proper attitude is compassion, since they too suffer an identical fate. The truth of Christianity, according to Schopenhauer, lies in its early emphasis on renunciation of the world and an ascetic life. Although he failed to clarify how this asceticism could be achieved in the absence of freedom, Schopenhauer’s work includes a strong suggestion. Because human actions are explicable through motives, he equates motive with cause. Thus, causation may be rooted in intellectual concepts. As the individual recognizes the futility of existence, he or she can become compassionate toward others and accept the futility of desire.

Arthur Schopenhauer Biography (Survey of World Philosophers)

0111206086-Schopenhauer.jpgArthur Schopenhauer (Library of Congress) Published by Salem Press, Inc.

Article abstract: In the tradition of Immanuel Kant, Schopenhauer developed a pessimistic system of philosophy based upon the primacy of will.

Early Life

Arthur Schopenhauer was born on February 22, 1788, in the Hanseatic city of Danzig, then under nominal control of Poland. His father, Heinrich, was an affluent merchant of Dutch aristocratic lineage, cosmopolitan in outlook and republican in politics. After Danzig lost its freedom to Prussia in 1793, he moved his family and business to Hamburg. Schopenhauer’s mother, Johanna, also of Dutch descent, later became a successful Romantic novelist.

Because Heinrich Schopenhauer planned a mercantile career for his son, Arthur’s education emphasized modern languages, which came easily to him. At age nine, he was sent to Le Havre to learn French, the first of six foreign languages he mastered. In return for agreeing to enter a merchant firm as an apprentice, his father rewarded him with an extended tour—lasting nearly a year and a half—of England, Scotland, France, Switzerland, Austria, and Germany, an experience that strengthened his own cosmopolitan perspective and further developed his facility with languages.

As an apprentice and later a clerk, Schopenhauer found the work tedious and boring, and after the death of his father by drowning, presumed a suicide, in 1805, he altered his life’s goals. With an inheritance adequate to assure independence and with encouragement from his mother, he entered grammar school at Gotha and then studied under tutors in Weimar, mastering Latin and Greek. At age twenty-one, he enrolled as a medical student in the University of Göttingen, changing to philosophy in his second year. His first influential teacher, G. E. Schulze, advised him to concentrate on Plato and Immanuel Kant, the two thinkers who would exert the strongest impact on his philosophy.

In 1811, Schopenhauer attended lectures at the University of Berlin by Johann Gottlieb Fichte and Friedrich Schleiermacher; scathing responses in his notes set the tone of his lifelong contempt for German academic philosophy. When revolution against Napoleonic rule flared in Berlin, Schopenhauer fled to the village of Rudolstadt, where he wrote his dissertation for a doctorate from the University of Jena. In On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, he explores types of causation: physical, logical, mathematical, and moral.

After receiving his doctorate, Schopenhauer returned to Weimar to live in his mother’s house, but the two could not agree. She found him moody, surly, and sarcastic; he found her vain and shallow. Disagreements and quarrels led her to dismiss him, and he left to establish his residence in Dresden in 1814, there to begin his major philosophical work. For the remaining twenty-four years of Johanna Schopenhauer’s life, mother and son did not meet.

Life’s Work

In Dresden, after completing a brief treatise on the nature of color, Schopenhauer was ready to begin serious preparation of his greatest philosophical work, The World as Will and Idea. Its three books, with an appendix on Kantian philosophy, include the conceptual ideas that Schopenhauer developed and elaborated throughout his career as an independent philosopher. Book 1 explains the world, everything that the mind perceives, as representation, a mental construct of the subject. Through perception, reasoning, and reflection and by placing external reality within the mental categories of time, space, and causality, one understands how the world operates. Yet one never understands reality as it exists, for the subjective remains an essential element of all perception.

The fundamental reality that eludes understanding is, as book 2 makes plain, the will, that Kantian thing-in-itself. Understood in its broadest sense, will exists in everything—as a life force and much more. In plants, it drives growth, change, and reproduction. In animals, it includes all of these as well as sensation, instinct, and limited intelligence. Only in humans does the will become self-conscious, through reflection and analysis, though the will is by no means free in the usual sense. Every action is determined by motives—to Schopenhauer another name for causes—that predetermine one’s choices. Thus, one may will to choose but not will to will. With its conscious and unconscious drives, will presses each person toward egoistic individualism; yet demands of the will, far from bringing peace, well-being, and gratification, lead only to additional struggle and exertion. As a consequence, unhappiness in life inevitably exceeds happiness.

As a respite from the imperious demands of the will, people find solace in the beauty that exists in nature and art, and the awakening of the aesthetic sense serves to tame the will by leading it toward disinterested contemplation. To enter a room and discover a table filled with food is to anticipate involvement, consumption, and interaction with others. To look at a painting of the same scene invites simply reflection and appreciation, removing any practical considerations from the will, thereby suspending its feverish activity.

Yet the solace afforded by beauty is only temporary. In book 4, Schopenhauer explores saintliness, which implies denial and permanent taming of the will. By recognizing that others experience the same unrelenting strife that the will creates in oneself, one can develop compassion. Through the power of reflection, one can recognize one’s own motives and,...

(The entire section is 2288 words.)

Arthur Schopenhauer Biography (Great Authors of World Literature, Critical Edition)

ph_0111206086-Schopenhauer.jpgArthur Schopenhauer Published by Salem Press, Inc.

Arthur Schopenhauer (SHOH-puhn-how-ur), the unacademic, misogynistic self-glorifying “philosopher of pessimism,” was born into a rich merchant family in the free city of Danzig. His father, Heinrich Schopenhauer, was a liberal thinker, a Voltairean, who admired England and feared that Prussia would annex Danzig. When his fears were realized in 1793, the Schopenhauers hurriedly moved to Hamburg. Arthur lived there with his family for four years until, at the age of nine, he was placed with a French family in Le Havre so that he might learn the French language for its commercial value.

In 1803, when he was fifteen, he was placed with an English cleric’s family and attended the local boarding school. He was...

(The entire section is 500 words.)