Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic Analysis

Benedetto Croce


(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Benedetto Croce’s Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic is the first of four volumes in his Filosofia come sciensa dello spirito (“philosophy of spirit”); the other three are Logica come scienza del concetto puro (1909; Logic as the Science of the Pure Concept, 1917), Filosofia della pratica: Economica ed etica (1909; Philosophy of the Practical: Economic and Ethic, 1913), and Teoria e storia della storiografia (1917; Theory and History of Historiography, 1921). Croce is generally regarded as an inspired proponent of the idealist strain in philosophy, and Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic, the introduction to his theory, continues to be the work for which he is best known, and it is by his aesthetic theory that he is judged.

The entire thesis of Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic rests on the concept of intuition, and because of the ambiguity of that term, Croce’s work in translation never received the critical attention that the original Italian did. No English term, used without careful qualification, has enough levels of meaning, enough systematic ambiguity, to carry the burden of Croce’s central idea. If, in addition, as may very well be the case, one must bring to the reading of Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic a certain tolerance of mind that the prevailing empiricist temper makes difficult, it becomes even more evident that one must resist the temptation to understand Croce all at once. The idea, however deceptively direct its initial expression, must be built with great care, according to Croce’s plan.

With this warning in mind, it becomes possible to take certain phrases as initial statements of Croce’s position, retaining them as expressions to be illuminated by further discussion and reflection, for otherwise they are practically meaningless. Thus, for Croce, art is intuition; intuition is expression; art is the expression of impressions; and expression is the objectification of feelings by way of representative images. Many negations follow from these affirmations; of them, the most important, for those who would understand Croce, is the denial that the work of art is a physical object.

Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic Art as Intuition

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

Croce begins Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic with a careful elaboration of the distinction between intuitive and logical knowledge; it is a distinction that bears some resemblance to philosopher Henri Bergson’s distinction between intuitive and scientific or conceptual knowledge, but there is a difference. Bergson argued that certain matters cannot be understood analytically or by classes; they must be felt, in their internal particularity—to know by being is intuition. For Croce, the distinction between the object as known from the outside and as realized by itself is not the critical distinction, although it is encompassed by the distinction he does stress. For Croce, intuitive knowledge is the possession of images, but of images clarified by the attention of spirit, freed of all vagueness by the act of apprehension. The idea is remarkable enough to need and deserve amplification, and fortunately there are examples that clarify Croce’s idea of intuition.

Croce asks how a person can be said to have an intuition of a geometrical figure or of the contour of the island of Sicily, if he cannot draw it. The notion that the artist is skilled in the act of transferring an image from the mind to some physical surface, as if his peculiar gift were in the handling of a pencil or brush, is repudiated by Croce. Unless one possesses a sensation or impression contemplatively, realizing it as an individual image, expression has not taken place. Under the influence of sentiment, one may suppose that one intuits, but unless one knows an image as an expression, one deceives oneself.

To enforce his point, Croce points out that the term “expression” is generally limited to verbal expression, but he uses it to cover nonverbal expressions of line, color, and sound. Apparently, for Croce, expression is not merely the clear apprehension of an image; the image is expressive of the feeling that it evokes, and it is through the expression of feeling that it becomes full expression or intuition. Thus, in Breviario di estetica (1913; The Breviary of Aesthetic, 1915), Croce writes that “what gives coherence and unity to the intuition is feeling: the intuition is really such because it represents a feeling, and can only appear from and upon that.” He then goes on to affirm that “Not the idea, but the feeling, is what confers on art the airy lightness of the symbol: an aspiration enclosed in the circle of a representation—that is art.”

The Breviary of Aesthetic, which is in many respects a superior expression of Croce’s aesthetic theory, is interesting because of the series of denials by which the positive import of Croce’s idea is brought out by...

(The entire section is 1128 words.)

Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic Values

(Student Guide to World Philosophy)

The beautiful, considered as aesthetic value, is defined by Croce as successful expression, but realizing that expression that is not successful is not expression, Croce concludes by writing that beauty is expression. Consequently, the ugly is unsuccessful expression, or the failure to achieve expression.

Corresponding to the polar values of beauty and ugliness in the aesthetic are the values of truth and falsity for the intellectual, the useful and the useless for the economic, and the just (or good) and unjust (or evil) for the moral. In every case, the positive value results from the successful development of spiritual activity.

Croce’s central criticism of any form of aesthetic hedonism—of any theory that regards art as the production of the pleasurable—is that aesthetic hedonism fails to distinguish between the beautiful, which is the pleasurable as expression, and other sources of pleasure. He scornfully rejects any theory that finds the source of artistic activity in the sexual, in the desire to conquer. He admits that “one often meets in ordinary life poets who adorn themselves with their poetry, like cocks that raise their crests,” but he argues that such a person is not a poet, but “a poor devil of a cock or turkey.”

For Croce, the physical reproduction of intuitions, the making of physical objects that will stimulate those who experience them to the activity of recreating the intuitions, is an aid...

(The entire section is 552 words.)

Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic Bibliography

(Critical Survey of Literature, Revised Edition)

Additional Reading

Brown, Merle E. Neo-Idealistic Aesthetics: Croce-Gentile-Collingwood. Detroit. Mich.: Wayne State University Press, 1966. The author devotes the first five chapters of this work, more than half the entire book, to Benedetto Croce. He emphasizes the development of Croce’s theory of art, which began with the view that art is representation and culminated by arguing that it is feeling objectified. The author addresses the influence of Giovanni Gentile on Croce’s changing views.

Casale, Giuseppe. Benedetto Croce Between Naples and Europe. New York: Peter Lang, 1993. The author argues that Croce sought to offer through his concept of historicism an alternative to both traditional religion and the culture of science. He places Croce’s ideas within the context of both Neapolitan and European culture.

Moss, M. E. Benedetto Croce Reconsidered: Truth and Error in Theories of Art, Literature, and History. Foreword by Maurice Mandelbaum. Hanover, N.H.: University Press of New England, 1987. Arguing for Croce’s continuing philosophical significance, the author addresses his philosophical conceptions of truth, error, and objectivity and analyzes his theory of intuition.

Roberts, David D. Benedetto Croce and the Uses of Historicism. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987. This critical reassessment is the best intellectual biography of Croce available in English. The author includes an impressive bibliography, covering major themes of modern European intellectual history.

Ryn, Claes G. Will, Imagination, and Reason: Babbitt, Croce, and the Problem of Reality. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1997. A good assessment of Croce’s thought.

Sprigge, Cecil. Benedetto Croce: Man and Thinker. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1952. Sprigge’s admiring, though not uncritical, account of Croce’s life and thought is probably the best general biography of Croce available in English.

Ward, David. Antifascisms: Cultural Politics in Italy, 1943-46: Benedetto Croce and the Liberals, Carlo Levi and the “Actionists.” Madison, N.J.: Fairleigh Dickinson University Press, 1996. A valuable treatment of Croce’s political philosophy.